• 110492阅读
  • 190回复

ethics of civilization

级别: 管理员
只看该作者 110 发表于: 2009-03-15
SOCRATES
Style and Methods
Style and Approach
Individualized Instruction
Questions and Answers
Poetry and Metaphor
Discussion
This chapter has been published in the book CONFUCIUS AND SOCRATES Teaching Wisdom. For ordering information, please click here.

Now that we have looked at the life and character of Socrates, we can turn to an examination of his particular approach in educating. What techniques did he use to facilitate learning?

Style and Approach
Socrates' attitude toward the divine carried over into his discussions as he often would pray for assistance in the argument or rely on his spiritual inspiration for guidance. In the Timaeus he suggested to Timaeus before he began his long speech that he should duly invoke the gods. Timaeus agreed that it is the intelligent way to begin any undertaking.1 In the Republic Socrates suggested to Glaucon that they pray for success in their search for justice.2 At the conclusion of the Phaedrus Socrates offered up a prayer to the gods of this enchanted place where he had been inspired. His prayer is characteristic of his values, but Phaedrus did agree to share it with his friend.

O beloved Pan (All) and the other gods of this place,
grant to me that I be made beautiful in my soul within,
and may the outward be in harmony with the inner person.
May I consider the wise person wealthy;
and may I have as much money
as a self-controlled person can bear and carry.3

Although Socrates saw himself as a catalyst or midwife, he felt it was actually the power of God which enabled the person he was talking with to improve. In the Alcibiades I In the Alcibiades I Socrates suggested to Alcibiades that he answer the questions put to him and "by God's will-if we are to put any trust in my divination-you and I shall both improve."4 As Socrates led Alcibiades on to the recognition of his need of education, he asked Alcibiades how he would proceed. Alcibiades responded that he depended on what Socrates wished, but Socrates corrected him by saying that it depended on God's will.5 In the Theages there is a lengthy description of several incidents where Socrates counseled his friends when he received an indication from his divine sign. Socrates twice warned another Timarchus not to leave a drinking party, but the third time Timarchus slipped out unnoticed and went to commit a crime for which he was later executed. He warned the commander, Sannio, not to set out on an expedition, and later the man was condemned to death after the battle of Arginusae.6 Then Socrates explained how the spiritual power assisted some in the educational process with him.

This spiritual power that attends me
also exerts itself to the full in my intercourse
with those who spend their time with me.
To many, indeed, it is adverse,
and it is not possible for these
to get any good by conversing with me,
and I am therefore unable to spend any time
in conversing with them.
And there are many with whom
it does not prohibit my intercourse,
yet the intercourse does them no good.
But those who are assisted
in their intercourse by that spiritual power
are the persons whom you have noticed;
for they make rapid progress there and then.
And of these, again, who make progress
some find the benefit both solid and enduring;
while there are many who,
for as long a time as they are with me,
make wonderful progress,
but when they are parted from me relapse,
and are no different from anybody else.7

Socrates cited Aristides as an example of one who improved and then after leaving Socrates, gradually felt his new abilities slipping away. Aristides related that although he did not learn anything from Socrates, he made progress whenever he was with Socrates-even if he was just in the same house, but more when in the same room, even more when he looked at Socrates as he spoke, and most of all when he sat beside him and touched him. In conclusion, Socrates told Theages that he would make rapid progress with him only if God willed it.8

When in the Phaedo Cebes praised Socrates for how well he handled the argument about the soul being a harmony, and expressed confidence for the next problem, Socrates warned him not to be boastful and allow negativity in; the argument was "in the hands of God."9

In the Cratylus, a tongue-in-cheek, half-humorous discussion of the origin of words and names, Socrates felt inspired, but he was not sure about the source of the inspiration.10 Later on Socrates recognized an intuition that came to him concerning the mutability and movement of all things.11 Further on again Socrates marveled at the wisdom of what he was saying, but at this point he felt the need to examine them more closely to avoid the worst of all deceptions-self-deception.12 Thus Socrates did not rely solely on inspiration, as we find him predominantly concerned with reasoning. Yet it is fair to say that he recognized and utilized divine sources of inspiration.

An important piece of evidence which supports that Socrates relied on divine inspiration to help others is found in a fragment from Aeschines, another Socratic whose writings were almost all lost. As a student of Socrates, Aeschines can be placed on a comparable level with Plato and Xenophon as to his opportunity to observe Socrates directly. Socrates here drew his conclusions as to how he had been able to help Alcibiades.

If I thought I knew some art
by which I could do good to people,
I should have charged myself with great folly:
but, as it is, I thought that these things came to me
as a divine gift for the sake of Alcibiades.
And there is nothing that calls for surprise in that....
Through the love which I felt for Alcibiades
I had had the same experience as the Bacchae.
For the Bacchae, when they are inspired,
draw up milk and honey from the wells
from which other people cannot even get water.
And so I too, though I have no science
with which I could help a person by instructing one in it,
nevertheless felt that by being with him
I could make him better through my love for him.13

Here we see also the love as the most important thing that Socrates was able to contribute.


For Socrates love and friendship were the proper contexts for the pursuit of wisdom and goodness. In Xenophon's Memoirs of Socrates he explained to Antiphon that to take money for his conversation would be like prostitution of wisdom instead of beauty. The duty of a gentleman is to help one's friends become as good as they can.14 In the Theaetetus Socrates was eager to discuss, but only in an atmosphere of friendship; he was very polite to Theodorus and did not try to force him into the argument against his will.15

In the Phaedo Socrates demonstrated how he was sensitive to the mood of the group and how he could understand the problem and allay their fears. After Simmias and Cebes had presented strong arguments against the immortality of the soul, several of his listeners began to have serious doubts. Phaedo described how Socrates handled the situation:

So his having an argument was perhaps not unexpected;
but I was especially amazed
first at how pleasantly and gently and respectfully
he accepted the argument of the youths,
then how he perceived how sharply
we were convinced by the arguments,
then how well he healed us
and as though he called us up from flight and defeat
and turned us forward toward it
he persuaded us also to consider together the argument.16

Phaedo went on to tell how Socrates stroked his beautiful hair and playfully suggested that they both should cut off their hair if they were not able to revive the wounded argument. Socrates knew how to relieve the tension when necessary.

In the Laches Socrates politely allowed the older gentlemen to speak first,17 and later he advised Laches to instruct Nicias if he was wrong, rather than abuse him.18 At the beginning of Xenophon's Symposium Callias invited Socrates and his companions to a banquet. Socrates admitted that he was only an amateur compared to the sophists whom Callias had paid much money such as Protagoras, Gorgias, Prodicus, and others. He was about to refuse the invitation, but seeing that this would really upset Callias, he agreed to go with him.19 Socrates was quite sensitive to the feelings of others and took them into consideration.

Xenophon's description of this banquet offers some of the best examples of Socrates' sense of humor. As they are playing the game of saying what they each pride themselves in most, Charmides claimed his was his poverty. Socrates commented, "It seldom causes envy or a quarrel; and it is kept safe without necessity of a guard, and grows stronger by neglect!"20 Then when asked by Callias, Socrates declared he was most proud of being a procurer. After they laughed, he claimed he could make much money in that trade.21 Xenophon recalled that Socrates often used to talk in a manner that was half joking and half serious.22

In the Euthyphro Socrates joked with the pious man about his arguments being like the statues of Daedalus, which were said to be so alive that they would run away and could not be held in a fixed place.23 In the Euthydemus when Dionysodorus and Ctesippus were getting into a bitter argument, Socrates noticed it and began to joke with his friend Ctesippus and gradually turned the discussion toward a desire for goodness.24

Socrates also had exceptional perseverance in carrying out an investigation of any subject. After Euthyphro's attempts to define holiness were found wanting, Socrates was ready to begin the inquiry again so that he might learn what holiness really is from this man who appeared to be so pious. However, Euthyphro begged off, and hurried away.25In the Philebus Protarchus asked Socrates three times to explain a point more clearly so that he could understand it. Even then he was still confused, but Socrates did not lose patience with him, as he went on to give another example.26

Socrates also demonstrated things by his own personal example. According to Diogenes Laertius, he once got up and left the theater during Euripides' Auge when the following statement was made about virtue: "'Tis best to let her roam at will." He said it was ridiculous to make a fuss about a slave who could not be found while virtue was allowed to be lost.27 When he had invited some rich men over and Xanthippe was ashamed of the dinner, he told her not to worry. If they were temperate, they would put up with it; and if they were not, they need not care about them. Socrates always demonstrated his own moderation and self-control of appetites. He used to say that while other people lived to eat, he himself ate to live.28

Xenophon also commented on Socrates' behavior and lessons at banquets. Socrates used to tell the waiter of the dining-club that the meat each person contributed should be put in the common stock. This discouraged some from spending much on meat. When one man ate meat without bread, Socrates mentioned this practice as an apt description of greed. When the man began to take some bread with his meat, Socrates suggested they watch to "see whether he treats the bread as his meat or the meat as his bread." He also cautioned that mixing the dishes destroyed the chef's art and dulled the appreciation of less variety.29 In Xenophon's Symposium Socrates recommended wine in moderation to induce a more sportive mood. However, plants when they are drenched with too much water become weak and fall over; so too should people avoid the excesses of wine which cause the bodies and minds to reel, making speech much less sensible.30

After describing Socrates' control of his own passions and appetites, Xenophon summarized the example that Socrates set.

Such was his own character:
how then can he have led others into
impiety, crime, gluttony, lust, or laziness?
On the contrary, he cured these vices in many,
by putting into them a desire for goodness,
and by giving them confidence
that self-discipline would make them gentlemen.
To be sure he never professed to teach this;
but, by letting his own light shine,
he led his disciples to hope that
they through imitation of him
would attain to such excellence.
Furthermore, he himself never neglected the body,
and criticized such neglect in others.
Thus over-eating followed by over-exertion he disapproved.
But he approved of taking as much hard exercise
as is agreeable to the soul;
for the habit not only insured good health,
but did not hinder the care of the soul.31

Xenophon continued on and explained that Socrates kept himself free by not accepting money for his conversation. He never promised anything, but he was confident that as gentlemen they could benefit from each others' friendship.32

This continual movement toward a better life was the energy which motivated Socrates. One of his major techniques was to encourage and exhort his listeners toward a virtuous life. In Xenophon's Defense of Socrates he said he had "served those who conversed with me by teaching them, without reward, every good thing that was in my power."33 In Xenophon's Symposium Socrates turned a discussion on perfume to the more lasting scent of the beauty and goodness of the soul. When Lycon asked where this ointment can be found, Socrates quoted Theognis:

Good people teach good; society with bad
Will but corrupt the good mind that you had.34

Later at the same banquet, Socrates praised and encouraged Callias in his spiritual rather than carnal love for Autolycus. Love of friendship and beautiful goodness (kalokagathia derives from "beauty and goodness" and is used to refer to noble conduct of a true gentleman) are related to the Heavenly Aphrodite as opposed to the Common Aphrodite. Hermogenes commented that by praising Callias in this way he was educating him in the ideal.35 Socrates used Callias' love to encourage him toward virtue.

The greatest blessing that befalls the one
who yearns to render his favorite a good friend
is the necessity of oneself
making virtue one's habitual practice.
For one cannot produce goodness in one's companion
while one's own conduct is evil,
nor can one exhibit shamelessness and incontinence
and at the same time render one's beloved
self-controlled and reverent.36

Finally Socrates urged Callias to learn and develop the abilities of such men as Themistocles, Pericles, and Solon so that he might become of great benefit to the city.37

In Plato's Charmides Socrates and his friends were attempting to discover the meaning of temperance or self-control. Socrates had an intuition that it is of some benefit, and therefore he was concerned not only to find out what it is, but what is its benefit as well.38 Even after being condemned to death, in Plato's Defense of Socrates we find Socrates giving a sermon to those who voted against him, suggesting that they make themselves as good as possible.39 To those who voted to acquit him, he made the request that they discipline his children and make sure they care more for virtue than anything else, as he, Socrates, had done for them.40

Socrates was particularly concerned with the proper education of the young. In the Laches Socrates was called upon to aid Lysimachus and Melesias in finding the best teachers for their sons. Socrates requested the assistance of Nicias and Laches, two famous generals, and he emphasized the value of a teacher who is so good that he can make the souls of young men good also.41 At the conclusion of the dialog Laches and Nicias agree that neither of them was as competent as Socrates, and Lysimachus asked Socrates to take on the task of improving the youths. However, Socrates admitted that he did not know the answers either, and therefore suggested that they all, even the elderly gentlemen, do everything they could to pursue their own education and that of the boys.42

Socrates was continually exhorting people not only to learn but to act virtuously. At the end of the Gorgias Socrates stressed the value and importance of justice, and he exhorted Callicles and all people to search to know the truth and to live as well as they can, practicing every virtue.43 In the Euthydemus Socrates gave the new sophists an example of how to exhort a youth to devote oneself to wisdom and virtue. By argument Socrates showed that everyone desires good things to be happy-not only the possession of good things, but the use of them-and wisdom is what enables us to use all things well, while ignorance leads to bad consequences. Therefore it is actually wisdom which makes all things good, and it is wisdom we should seek in order to be happy and be able to use things well.44

Additional exhortations are found in the Republic. Socrates differentiated the divine and reasoning aspect of the soul from the brutish appetites of the body, and then he encouraged the listeners to use wisdom and justice to govern oneself and harmonize the various levels of the person. The wise will use intelligence and self-control to rule over the lower instincts and attune the harmonies of the body for the sake of the concord in the soul as a true musician does.45 At the conclusion of this work Socrates encouraged everyone to "hold ever to the upward way and pursue righteousness with wisdom always."46

Socrates also urged people to be truthful and to search for the truth in discussion. In Plato's Symposium when Alcibiades was about to give his speech in praise of Socrates, he asked Socrates' permission to speak truthfully. Socrates not only permitted him to be candid, but exhorted him to be truthful.47 In the Phaedo Socrates gave an elaborate explanation of the danger in giving up the search for truth because of much experience with bad arguments. He warned them not to become haters of argument because of having been led astray many times. This could deprive us of the truth and knowledge of reality. Rather we should examine ourselves and make ourselves ready to receive the truth. Although on the day of his death Socrates was searching for the truth for selfish reasons, they should not allow themselves to care more for the opinions of Socrates than for the truth itself so that they all could avoid self-deception.48

Xenophon answered the criticisms that although Socrates was skilled in exhorting men to virtue, he was an incompetent guide to it, by recommending consideration of his searching cross-examinations of those who thought they knew everything and of his daily talks with his friends.49 Therefore let us now turn to an investigation of his various methods of instruction.

Individualized Instruction
Because Socrates was not a formal teacher with regular classes or an organized curriculum, his way of assisting people was spontaneous and specifically suited to the particular needs of the individual as he saw them. According to Xenophon, Socrates expended great effort to make people independent in doing the work for which they were most fit. To enable him to do this he sought

very carefully to discover
what each of his companions knew.
Whatever was appropriate for a gentleman to know
he taught most eagerly,
so far as his own knowledge extended;
if he was not entirely familiar with a subject,
he took them to those who knew.
He also taught them how far a well-educated person
should make oneself familiar with any given subject.50

In Xenophon's Defense of Socrates when Meletus accused Socrates of persuading the young men to obey him instead of their parents, Socrates admitted that it was true as far as education is concerned.51 In the same work Socrates mentioned that the reason Anytus became perturbed and charged Socrates with these crimes was because Socrates advised him not to limit his son's education to the tanning trade.52

Plato also gave examples of how Socrates used to recommend teachers to inquiring learners.In the Laches Socrates had a reputation for spending his time wherever there was excellent study or the pursuit of education. Nicias said Socrates introduced him to a superb music teacher, Damon, for his son.53 In the Protagoras a young Hippocrates asked Socrates to introduce him to the most eminent of the sophists. Socrates questioned Hippocrates to see what it was he hoped to learn from Protagoras. Education is a serious business because one is committing one's soul to another person, hoping to be improved in the process. After Socrates had questioned Hippocrates on these points, they agreed to go together to see.54 When they met with Protagoras, Socrates asked him on behalf of Hippocrates what he would learn and become better in if he associated with the sophist.55

Socrates made it his business to study which young men in Athens showed outstanding potential and what was their educational background. In the Theaetetus he inquired of the geometrician Theodorus whether there are any excellent prospects.56

Once Socrates had engaged in conversation with anyone, young or old, he usually turned the discussion toward the person oneself and how one led one's life. In the Laches Nicias gave Lysimachus a description of what he expected Socrates would do.

You seem to me not to be aware
that whoever comes nearest to Socrates
and enters into conversation with him
is liable to be drawn round and round by him
in the course of the argument-
no matter on what subject it began-not stopping
until one is led into giving an account of oneself,
of how one spends one's days,
and of the kind of life one has lived in the past;
and once one has been entangled in that,
Socrates will not let one go until
he has thoroughly and properly put all one's ways to the test.57

In Xenophon's Symposium Socrates recommended that although the musical entertainment was pleasurable, perhaps they ought to help and please each other. They agreed, and so he suggested they share what each of them considered to be his most valuable knowledge.58 In other words, Socrates tended to direct the activity to some sort of self-knowledge or self-examination.

Socrates often gave individuals advice in regard to certain problems in their lives. Diogenes Laertius gave us several anecdotes. When he observed that Aeschines was suffering from poverty, Socrates suggested he borrow from himself by reducing his meals.59 When his son Lamprocles became violently angry with his mother, Socrates made him feel ashamed of himself. He advised Glaucon, Plato's brother, who was eager to go into politics, not to, because of his lack of experience; but he encouraged Charmides to take it up because he had a talent for politics. He warned Euclides, who was fascinated with eristic arguments, that it would enable him to get along with sophists, but not with people.60

Xenophon gave many examples of how Socrates advised individuals in specific ways. Often his advice was just common sense, which sometimes escaped people somehow. Xenophon also showed us the practical side of Socrates. When Socrates observed that a man became angry because his greeting was not returned, he said, "Ridiculous! You would not have been angry if you had met a man in worse health; and yet you are annoyed because you have come across someone with ruder manners!"61 To a man who grew tired of eating, he suggested, "Stop eating; and you will then find life pleasanter, cheaper, and healthier."62 Obviously, people do not need to be counseled to eat. Another man complained that his water was too warm for drinking and too cold for bathing, even though his servants did not mind it. Socrates reminded him that Epidaurus water was warmer to drink and Oropus water colder for washing, and that apparently this man was harder to please than servants and invalids.63

When a man beat his footman for being gluttonous, foolish, rapacious, and lazy, Socrates asked him to consider whether the slave or the master should bear the responsibility and the punishment.64 When someone was dreading the long walk to Olympia, Socrates reminded him that it is like taking a walk before lunch and another before dinner. Rather than trying to hurry, it could be much more pleasant by planning to leave a day early and then taking it easy.65 Another man was exhausted after a long journey. Socrates inquired who carried the baggage. It was the slave and not the man; he said he never could have done it. Then Socrates wondered whether a trained man should be less capable than his slave.66

Socrates advised an old friend, Eutherus, who had lost everything in the war, to hire himself out in some business to a considerate employer so that he would have something to live on in his old age.67 Socrates' good friend Crito complained to him that unscrupulous men were always taking him to court to get money from him, knowing that he would pay rather than be bothered. Socrates suggested he get a dog to keep the wolves away from his sheep. So they sought out Archedemus, an honest man and good speaker, but poor. Crito made him his friend, giving him a percentage of his corn, oil, wine, wool, and other produce. Archedemus then discovered that Crito's false accusers had committed many crimes. He charged them in court and would not let them off until they dropped their actions against Crito and compensated him. Soon Archedemus became the protector for many of Crito's friends as well.68

Socrates was not afraid to criticize his friends or those in power if he felt they needed it. At one time Critias was among the circle of Socrates and had fallen in love with Euthydemus. He could not keep his hands off of him, and Socrates felt he was leading him astray. Therefore he said in the presence of Euthydemus and others, "Critias seems to have the feelings of a pig: he can no more keep away from Euthydemus than pigs can help rubbing themselves against stones."69 Consequently Critias bore a grudge against Socrates; and when he was in the government of the Thirty, he and Charicles made it illegal "to teach the art of words."70 However, this did not stop Socrates, who seeing that the Thirty were putting to death many respectable citizens, remarked,

It seems strange enough to me that a herdsman
who lets his cattle decrease and go to the bad
should not admit that he is a poor cowherd;
but stranger still that a statesman
when he causes the citizens to decrease and go to the bad,
should feel no shame nor think himself a poor statesman.71

Xenophon showed that this comment got to Critias' ears by recording the conversation between Critias and Charicles and Socrates when Socrates was called before them on the law forbidding conversation with the young. Socrates asked if he must abstain from sound or unsound reasoning. They replied that he must not speak at all to anyone under the age of thirty. Socrates then asked if he might inquire from a young person the price of an item or simple directions. These were permissible, but he must keep off his favorite topics of cobblers, builders, workers, and subjects such as justice and holiness. Then Critias added, "And cowherds too: or else you may find the cattle decrease."72

One day Socrates noticed that Aristarchus looked sad, and so he offered to share the burden with him. Aristarchus explained that since the revolution his household was filled with his female relatives-fourteen in the house altogether. They were in danger of starving because nobody was buying property. and he could not get a loan. Socrates pointed out a man who had a large household and was becoming rich. Aristarchus said it was because his family was made up of free citizens with a liberal education, while the other man had slaves with crafts. Socrates asked if this was not disgraceful that the free should be worse off than slaves. Certainly his relatives had learned to make bread, cloaks, shirts, and other items. Socrates pointed out several families that were supported in these ways. He showed how much happier they would be to be doing useful work to support themselves rather than sitting in gloomy idleness, suspicious of each other. Surely this work is honorable. Aristarchus then was able to get a loan with this purpose in mind, and soon the women in his house were busy all day and smiling. Aristarchus returned to Socrates with the good news, but he felt guilty that now he was the only one in the household who ate the bread of idleness. So Socrates told him the story of the dog who was given food by the master even though he provided no wool or lambs or cheese as the sheep did. However, he was their watchdog and keeper who protected them all.73

In his Anabasis Xenophon recorded how he asked for Socrates' advice on what was probably one of the most important decisions of his life-whether he should join the expedition with Cyrus. Socrates suspected that his siding with Cyrus might make him an enemy to Athenians since Cyrus had supported the Lacedaemonians in their war against Athens. Therefore he advised Xenophon to consult the Delphic oracle concerning the journey. However, Xenophon only asked to what gods he should sacrifice and pray in order to have a successful journey. When Xenophon reported back to Socrates, he criticized the young man for deciding himself to go rather than first asking the oracle whether or not he should go at all. Under the circumstances Socrates accepted the result and advised, "However, since you did put the question in that way, you must do all that the god directed."74

According to Xenophon, Socrates gave Aristippus lengthy counseling on his pleasurable way of life. After showing that rulers must be trained in self-control more than those who are ruled, Socrates asked Aristippus in which group he placed himself. Aristippus admitted that he had no desire to be a ruler. Then Socrates asked him if he preferred the life of the ruled nations of the world. Aristippus had no taste for slavery, but chose a middle path through liberty, which leads to happiness. However, Socrates was not certain that he could avoid the world and the strong who oppress the weak. Aristippus declared that he owed no allegiance to any state, but he was a stranger in every land. Yet again, this was no proof against injury because he did not have the protection or rank of citizenship. Socrates asked him how masters treat servants who do no work yet want luxuries. Aristippus answered that he himself made their lives a burden until they obeyed. Nonetheless he felt compulsory punishment was no better and less foolish than voluntary suffering.

Socrates, however, pointed out the rewards of using one's will to work hard and accomplish certain prizes, such as winning friends, subduing enemies, making oneself capable in body and soul of managing one's household well, of helping friends, and serving one's country. These could bring joy, contentment, praise, and honor. He quoted Hesiod about how evil is easily found, but it takes hard work to become virtuous; though once the long and steep path is climbed, on top the way becomes easy. Then Socrates narrated the long allegory by Prodicus of Heracles meeting two women on the road-Virtue and Vice. Vice offered immediate pleasures, but Virtue warned of their shallowness and urged Heracles toward a life of heroism which offered more lasting happiness. Finally Socrates advised, "Aristippus, it would be worthwhile for you to think about these things and try to consider well the life that is ahead of you."75 Aristippus turned out to be the pre-Epicurean of the Socratics.

In his Symposium Xenophon told us that Critobulus was given by his father into the care of Socrates so that he might be improved.76 In the Oikonomikos Socrates helped Critobulus to get an education in household management. Socrates admitted that he himself did not have experience in this field, but he could direct Critobulus to someone who was especially skilled in this art. In fact Socrates declared that he had made it a study of his to discover "who are the greatest masters of various sciences to be found in Athens."77 In this way he had directed many young men to teachers who had been successful in their pursuits. Socrates suggested that Critobulus study exactly how successful men conduct their business, just as someone might study tragedies and comedies to learn to be a playwright. Critobulus had eagerly enjoyed many plays and seen successful businessmen, but he had not made a careful study to see precisely how they handle things. Socrates said that the management of a household depended a great deal on the wife, and the skill of the wife depended on how the husband treated her. Socrates offered to take Critobulus to see Aspasia who had more knowledge in this matter than Socrates. Usually the income was a result of the man's efforts, but expenditures were often controlled by the wife. If they both cooperated and did well, the estate increased. Socrates added, "If you think you want to know about other branches of knowledge, I suppose I can show you people who handle themselves creditably in any one of them."78
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 111 发表于: 2009-03-15
In his recollections of Socrates, Xenophon gave us a detailed case study of how Socrates began an educational process with Euthydemus. Xenophon presented it as a typical example of Socrates' "methods of dealing with those who thought they had received the best education, and prided themselves on wisdom."79 Euthydemus had collected many books which contained the wisdom of the ages, and he was confident in the abilities of speech and action. Socrates observed that he did not enter the market-place because of his youth, but he sat in the saddler's shop. Therefore Socrates went to this shop with some of his companions. Someone asked whether Themistocles became great by natural ability or by studying with a wise man. To get Euthydemus thinking, Socrates said, "If in the minor arts great achievement is impossible without competent masters, surely it is absurd to imagine that the art of statesmanship, the greatest of all accomplishments, comes to a person of its own accord."80

On another occasion, Euthydemus was reluctant to join the circle of Socrates or to show any admiration for his wisdom. Socrates told the group that when Euthydemus was of an age he would not hesitate to offer the Athenian Assembly advice on some policy. Then Socrates satirized Euthydemus' attitude of not wanting to be indebted to anyone for his knowledge by reciting the speech Euthydemus would give. He explained how he had never learned anything from anyone, but he would recommend whatever pops into his head. Socrates made it even more humorous by adapting it to the office of public physician. He had never studied medicine, but he would like to be appointed physician so that he could try to learn by experimenting on them. This gave them all a good laugh. Having gotten his attention, Euthydemus still remained quiet; so Socrates commented how strange it is that although musicians require teachers and practice, those who would be good public speakers and politicians assume they need no training or study even though their task is more difficult.81

When Euthydemus became more tolerant of his conversation and attentive, Socrates decided to go see him alone. Finding him in the saddler's shop one day, Socrates asked him about his collection of books. Socrates was pleased that he was pursuing wisdom, and asked him what type of goodness he was looking for in these books. Was it the skill of a physician, architect, mathematician, astronomer, or rhapsodist? Euthydemus sought none of these. What he wanted was the excellence which makes a politician, manager, ruler, and benefactor of humanity. Socrates called this the royal art, and asked if it required justice. Euthydemus agreed that it does, and he claimed that he was a just man. Socrates proposed to test his knowledge of justice by making two lists with the just things in one column and the unjust in another column. They began by placing lying, deceit, mischief, and selling into slavery under the heading of injustice. Then Socrates asked him about the case of a general who did each of these things to an unjust and hostile state. Euthydemus admitted that then they would be just.
So Socrates proposed they revise their classification: that it is just to do such things to enemies, but unjust to friends towards whom one should be scrupulously honest. When Euthydemus agreed, Socrates gave examples of a general encouraging his men with a lie, a father deceiving his son by pretending the medicine he refused to take was food, and the friend who stole the sword from a man who was depressed and suicidal. Euthydemus again had to admit that straightforwardness with friends is not always right. Euthydemus was losing confidence in his answers, but he still held that intentional deception is more unjust than unintentional deception. By the analogy of knowing letters, Socrates showed that intentional deception is more knowledgeable, and because ignorance of what is good and just is slavish, Euthydemus was wrong again. Through this process of refutation, Euthydemus was brought to realize his own ignorance.

By the gods, Socrates, I did certainly believe that
I was a student of a philosophy that would provide me
with the best education in all things needed
by one who would be a gentleman.
But you can imagine my dismay when I realize
that in spite of all my trouble I am not even able
to answer a question about things I really ought to know,
and still have no other way
that will lead to my improvement.82

Now Socrates could bring up the importance of self-knowledge by mentioning the Delphic inscription: "Know yourself." Socrates asked Euthydemus if he paid attention to this and tried to consider who he is, but Euthydemus assumed he already knew or else he could hardly know anything else. Socrates suggested it might be helpful to know his own abilities and uses just as one who buys a horse wants to know whether it is docile or stubborn, strong or weak, fast or slow, and how useful it is as a horse. Euthydemus realized that because he did not know his own abilities, he must be ignorant of himself. Then Socrates explained the value of self-knowledge.

Is it not clear too that on account of self-knowledge
people come to much good,
and on account of self-deception to much harm?
For those who know themselves,
know what things are suitable for themselves
and discern their own abilities and limitations.
And by doing what they understand,
they get what they want and prosper;
by refraining from attempting what they do not understand,
they make no mistakes and avoid failure.
And consequently through their ability to test other people too,
and through their relationships with others
they get what is good and watch out for what is bad.
Those who do not know and are deceived
in their estimate of their own abilities,
are in the same condition with regard to
other people and other human affairs.
They know neither what they want, nor what they do,
nor those with whom they have relationships;
but mistaken in all these respects,
they miss the good and fall into the bad.
Furthermore, those who know what they do
win fame and honor by attaining their goals.
Their equals are glad to have dealings with them;
and those who miss their objectives look to them for counsel,
look to them for protection,
rest on them their hopes of better things,
and for all these reasons love them above all others.
But those who do not know what they do,
choose badly, fail in what they attempt and,
besides incurring direct loss and punishment,
they earn contempt through their failures,
make themselves ridiculous,
and live in dishonor and humiliation.83

The same is true of communities if they are to solve effectively their problems and relate well to other communities.

Now Euthydemus recognized the importance of self-knowledge and asked Socrates how he might begin the process of self-examination. Socrates asked him if he knew the difference between what is good and what is bad. Euthydemus assumed that he did, and stated to Socrates that health is good and sickness is bad. However, Socrates cited cases of where the healthy have had to fight in fatal wars while the sick stayed home. Since the healthy had also had success in adventures, we could not say that health necessarily leads to good or bad fortune. Euthydemus suggested that wisdom is always a good thing, but Socrates mentioned how Daedalus, Palamedes, and others were enslaved, killed, and persecuted on account of their wisdom. Happiness would be good except that its elements of beauty, strength, wealth, glory, and other like qualities have been sources of trouble for mankind. Since Euthydemus is planning to go into democratic government, Socrates asked him if he knew the people, rich and poor. Euthydemus said the poor did not have enough to pay for what they want, while the rich had more than enough. However, Socrates pointed out that some who had little could still save while others no matter how much they had could not live within their means. Finally Euthydemus realized his stupidity and decided he had better not say anything more. Thus he went away dejected and disgusted with himself.84

Xenophon mentioned that many people who were brought to this state, never went back to Socrates, and they were regarded as stupid by him. However, Euthydemus realized that he would never amount to anything unless he spent as much time as possible with Socrates. From then on he never left him and began to emulate some of his practices. "Socrates, seeing how it was with him, avoided worrying him, and began to expound very plainly and clearly the knowledge that he thought most needful and the practices that he held to be most excellent."85 This indicates that the negative cross-examination, though perhaps the most interesting, was not the limit of Socrates' educating, as he went on to give positive teachings as well.

A very similar case study is found in the Alcibiades I which has been attributed to Plato. In this dialog Socrates announced his love for Alcibiades now that he had grown to manhood and was ready to listen. Socrates correctly diagnosed Alcibiades' political ambitions and offered to help educate the young man so that he can attain his goals. He simply asked Alcibiades to answer the questions put to him. Socrates began by inquiring whether Alcibiades had the knowledge needed for him to give good advice to the Athenians. Alcibiades claimed to know what is better and what is just, but under Socrates' cross-examination it became apparent that he did not. Since Alcibiades was the one answering the questions, the admissions he was making were coming from himself of his own free will. Socrates even offered him the choice of asking or answering, but they agreed that by answering he was being persuaded by himself instead of another.86

Soon Alcibiades too was in complete confusion, and Socrates explained to him that it was not because he was simply ignorant, but because he thought he knew when he did not. Again, this is the dangerous self-deception which leads one to make mistakes. When Alcibiades discovered that there were no wise politicians who had been able to make others wise, he figured he might not need to be educated. This immediately aroused Socrates' concern for his friend and his desire to see him improve, so he motivated Alcibiades by appealing to his tremendous ambition and comparing the ideal education of the Persian prince to Alcibiades' predicament. Now Alcibiades was ready to learn and asked Socrates for assistance. Socrates recommended that they take counsel with each other so that they might become as good as they could.87

To improve himself, a person must first know what it is one wishes to improve. By asking him questions Socrates showed Alcibiades that it was not his possessions which he used, nor even his body which he, the self, also used, but the soul which is implied in the Delphic statement: "Know yourself." The crafts of physical objects and even the arts of the physician and trainer which care for the body are not the science of self-knowledge. The true lover of Alcibiades was not the one who loved the body, but the one who loved his soul and sought to help him become virtuous, and that was Socrates. How could one know oneself? Socrates suggested the analogy of the eye looking at the seeing part of the eye (its virtue). Therefore the soul should look at the virtuous and divine part of itself, namely wisdom and justice. By acting wisely and justly, he would be doing the will of God; or by looking in the mirror of the divine he would know himself and his own good, would act rightly and be happy. The conclusion was that Alcibiades should seek not power but virtue in order to accomplish his goals.88

Socrates demonstrated his sharp perception of other people in the Phaedrus when he asked the young man about the speech he had heard from Lysias. Phaedrus pretended that he was not able to remember or repeat the speech, but Socrates saw right through him. "O Phaedrus! If I don't know Phaedrus, I have forgotten myself."89 Socrates went on to describe how Phaedrus must have asked for the speech to be repeated several times, and then if he could, got hold of a written copy, making every attempt to memorize it. Then meeting another lover of discourse, he hoped to practice on him, but Socrates would have none of that and suggested to Phaedrus that he pull the speech out from under his cloak and read it aloud. Socrates was not fooled by words, but he was interested in discussing what was of particular interest to the other person.

In Plato's Symposium they all agreed to give a speech on love. However, after Agathon's speech and before his own, Socrates could hardly refrain from questioning Agathon on some particular points about love (Eros) being the love or desire of something one does not apparently have. Therefore love cannot simply be the good and beautiful as Agathon suggested. Agathon admitted that he could not refute Socrates, but Socrates corrected this by reminding him that Socrates could easily be refuted, but the truth could not be.90 Socrates did not like to miss an opportunity to help an individual clarify his ideas.

In the Theaetetus the young man by that name was described by Theodorus as having similar facial features to Socrates and being very quick to learn. When Socrates met Theaetetus, he immediately began questioning him on these points. However, since Theodorus was probably not an expert on faces, as he was not a painter, he passed quickly over this to examine Theaetetus on his learning ability and virtue.91

In the Meno there are several examples of how Socrates gave special attention to individuals and their interests and abilities. At the beginning Socrates declared that he did not know what virtue is; in fact he had not yet found anyone who did know. Meno suggested the sophist Gorgias whom Socrates heard also; but Socrates could not recall his knowing what virtue is. Since Meno admitted that he shared the views of Gorgias, Socrates suggested that they not deal with Gorgias, as he was not there.92 This way Socrates was able to relate directly with Meno and his awareness. Socrates further demonstrated his ability to work with various kinds of individuals by helping a slave boy to learn how to double the area of a square by making another square. This showed Meno that they ought to inquire into what they did not know. However, they still did not know the nature of virtue. Yet Meno was now more interested in whether virtue could be taught or not. Socrates would prefer to first discover what virtue is, but he decided not to try to control Meno and yielded to Meno's desire to pursue this other question.93 When Anytus arrived on the scene, Socrates included him in the discussion by asking for his advice in finding a teacher of virtue for Meno. The conversation got around to the sophists, whom Anytus despises. Socrates asked him what experience with them he had to support his strong opinions against them. Anytus said he had had no dealings at all with them. After Socrates had made this point clear, he returned to the question of finding a teacher of virtue.94

Even during the time of his trial, Socrates could still put aside his own personal difficulties in order to discuss a question of concern to another person.In the Euthyphro Socrates was on his way to court when he discovered that Euthyphro was bringing a charge against his own father for unholy murder. Socrates surmised that Euthyphro must be an expert on religion and asked to become his student so that he could learn what holiness is.95 Socrates also suggested that Euthyphro present his case to him so that he could prepare for his speech before the judges.96 One might think Socrates had nothing else on his mind even though he was about to be tried for a capital crime!

Even in defending himself in court, Socrates endeavored to instruct Meletus by asking him how one should properly care for the youth and who does it. Also, if he corrupted them willingly, what possible motive could he have to injure? And if he corrupted them unwillingly, then he was in need, not of punishment, but of instruction so that he could consciously change his ways. Here Socrates demonstrated that he believed that education was the solution to ethical problems. On the religious question Socrates again concentrated on exactly what Meletus' conceptions were. He discovered that Meletus believed that he was an atheist. This idea he easily refuted by showing that Meletus was formally charging him with believing in new spiritual beings, an obvious contradiction of atheism.97

When Crito visited him in prison, Socrates seemed to be less concerned about his own fate than his friend was. Crito had come to help Socrates escape, but Socrates immediately focused on the ethical question of whether it would be right for him to try to escape. He could have said yes or no, but instead he debated the issue of concern to Crito with him. The process of inquiry then became instructional as many points were laid out which apparently Crito had not considered.98

As in the case of Alcibiades, Socrates could help to motivate another person to learn if he thought that the person could especially benefit from education. Xenophon recalled how valuable the companionship of Socrates was, even in his light moods as well as when he was serious. Socrates often said that he was in love with someone; but Xenophon was quick to point out that it was not with the outwardly beautiful but with those whose souls excelled in goodness and who were quick and eager to learn. He used different approaches for different individuals. To those who felt they had all the natural ability they needed without learning, he explained that the greater the natural gifts are, the greater is the need and value of education, just as the spirited thoroughbred horse requires the most training and is worse off without it. To the wealthy who thought money could replace education, he said,

Only a fool can think it possible to distinguish
between beneficial things and harmful things without learning:
only a fool can think that without distinguishing these
he will get all he wants by means of his wealth
and be able to do what is useful:
only a nitwit can think that
without the ability to do what is useful
he is doing well and has made good
or sufficient provision for his life:
only a nitwit can think that
by his wealth alone without knowledge
he will appear to be good at something,
or will enjoy a good reputation
without appearing to be good at anything in particular.99

In Plato's Lysis Socrates showed that a free person is usually only allowed to act freely in areas where one has knowledge and wisdom. Although Lysis was a free man, his parents did not trust him to handle many of the household affairs and possessions which they did trust to their slaves. However, in the areas in which Lysis had been educated, such as reading, writing, and music, he was the one they called upon. Socrates explained that even the prince of Asia would not be trusted by the great king to meddle with the soup or his own injured eyes in preference to a knowledgeable cook or physician. Thus knowledge and wisdom are the real license for doing things, and are what enable a person to be useful and beneficial to one's friends. Consequently Lysis realized that he needed to learn.100
Socrates then got the young man to thinking by refuting all the different understandings they could think of concerning what friendship is.101 This process of getting people to doubt whether what they assumed they knew is really true is a noted characteristic of the Socratic method. In another dialog Meno declared that Socrates was like the sting-ray which paralyzed his consciousness so that he could no longer define a concept such as virtue about which he had made many good speeches. Socrates agreed he paralyzed only if he added that he himself was thrown into doubt through this process. However, Socrates was still willing to go on inquiring and examining to see if they could discover the nature of what they were studying.102 The cross-examination, therefore, could serve as a motivator for further study.
Sometimes Socrates playfully encouraged others to study with him or search for greater wisdom by saying that he had a charm which he applied to cure the soul by fair words. In the Charmides Socrates explained that he was told by the Thracian king Zalmoxis not to cure the body without first using the charm to cure the soul; for if the soul is self-controlled and balanced, then the body can easily be brought back to health. Thus, to cure Charmides' headache Socrates must first charm his soul. After a lengthy cross-examination on temperance, or self-control, Socrates admitted that they were not understanding it fully and regretted he was unable to use the charm. However, Charmides was stimulated by the discussion and requested that Socrates charm him every day of his life.103 In the Phaedo Socrates made good his claim mentioned in the Charmides that the charm could even bring the awareness of immortality. When Simmias and Cebes were fearful that the soul might be dissolved by the wind, Socrates suggested that they sing charms to each other every day until they charm away the fear. Cebes asked where they could find such a good singer of charms now that Socrates was leaving them. Socrates recommended that they search in various countries regardless of the expense and that they also should seek among themselves, for they might be more able to do this than others.104 Even when Socrates was about to die, he was still encouraging others to seek the good life.

Questions and Answers
Socrates is famous for his method of asking questions in especially effective ways. Apparently he began to learn from the process of inquiry at a very young age. Although it was written a long time after its historical setting, Plato's Parmenides shows us a young Socrates questioning Zeno to learn what he meant in his writings. After listening to Zeno read his treatise through, he asked him to repeat his first point. Socrates then inquired of Zeno to clarify exactly the implication of what he had written-that the many are really one. Socrates then brought up the idea of abstractions and that things participate in them. He wondered whether the abstract ideas or intellectual conceptions could be united and separated as are visible objects. The respected Parmenides complimented Socrates on his skill in argument.105 Parmenides supported the notion of abstract ideas as being useful and necessary for carrying on arguments. Parmenides recommended that Socrates get further training in argument through testing a hypothesis by looking at what the results would be if it was true, or if it was not true. Socrates asked Parmenides to give him a demonstration of how this works.106

For Socrates the starting point was the realization that he did not know, and from there he could search for knowledge. In the Cratylus Hermogenes expected Socrates to convince him of the natural correctness of names, but Socrates reminded him, "You forget what I said a while ago, that I did not know, but would join you in looking for the truth."107 Realizing the difficulty during their discussion of finding the origin of names, especially foreign words, Socrates still felt it was worthwhile to pursue the scientific knowledge of names. After he gave his views, he asked to learn from Cratylus.108

In the Charmides Socrates reminded Critias twice that he did not know the answers to the questions, and this was why he inquired-for his own sake as well as others'. He suggested to Critias that they not be concerned about whether Critias or Socrates was being refuted, but rather: "Give the argument itself your attention, and observe what will become of it under the test of refutation."109 Thus he endeavored not to let personalities get in the way.

In the Theaetetus Socrates encouraged the young man to attempt to define knowledge. He looked upon Theaetetus as being pregnant and himself as a midwife. Socrates described midwives as being older and past child-bearing but not barren; they know better than anyone who is pregnant, can arouse labor pains or calm them, can perform an abortion if desirable, and are skillful matchmakers. How did Socrates' art compare to this? Socrates' patients sometimes gave birth to real ideas and other times to mere images. He practiced upon people rather than bodies. The most important aspect of his art was testing whether the mind of the young man was bringing forth false images or real and true children. Socrates considered himself to be sterile in wisdom and agreed with the criticism of him that he questioned others but did not answer himself. He said that God required him to be a midwife but had never allowed him to bring forth. Although he himself was not wise or inventive, those who associated with him, even the ones that seemed ignorant, as God was gracious to them, made wonderful progress. He said,

And it is clear that they do this,
not because they have ever learned anything from me,
but because they have found in themselves
many beautiful things and have brought them forth.
But the delivery is due to God and me.110

Evidence of this is that many had left Socrates, fallen in with evil companions, and ended up raising their offspring so badly that they lost them. After having explained his art, Socrates offered his assistance to Theaetetus.

Now I have said all this to you at such length, good sir,
because I suspect that you, as you yourself believe,
are in pain because you are pregnant with something within you.
Apply then to me, remembering that I am the son of a midwife
and have myself a midwife's gifts,
and do your best to answer the questions I ask as I ask them.
And if, when I have examined any of the things you say,
it should prove that I think it is a mere image and not real,
and therefore quietly take it from you and throw it away,
do not be angry as women are
when they are deprived of their first offspring.
For many before this have got into such a state of mind
towards me that they are actually ready to bite me,
if I take some foolish notion away from them;
and they do not believe that I do this in kindness,
since they are far from knowing that no god is unkind to mortals,
and that I do not do this from unkindness either,
and that it is quite out of the question
for me to allow an imposture or to destroy the true.
And so, Theaetetus, begin again
and try to tell us what knowledge is.
And never say that you are unable to do so;
for if God wills it and gives you courage, you will be able.111

After Socrates gave a long account of some of the theories of Protagoras, Theaetetus questioned his ability to understand whether Socrates was preaching these things because he believed them or whether he was testing Theaetetus. Socrates had to remind him that he knew nothing of these things, but that he was explaining these philosophical theories in order to help Theaetetus bring his own opinions to light. When this was accomplished, then they could test them to see if they were false or real.112 As Socrates questioned Theaetetus the idea was brought forth that perception is knowledge. Theodorus jumped in and asked Socrates if this was wrong. Again Socrates denied being able to make such a judgment, and he said that he was only able to extract an argument from the other person.113 Socrates would gladly question Theodorus, but he declined to answer. Not wishing to go against his will, Socrates resumed the questioning of Theaetetus on Protagoras' theories.

Then Socrates indicated that Theodorus was really the most capable of answering the questions at this point, and just as Critias had been drawn into the argument in the Charmides, Theodorus was no longer able to avoid giving an account of his ideas. Socrates got Theodorus to agree to propositions which contradicted the theory of Protagoras. They then looked at several other ideas and theories. Throughout, the responses of Theodorus were quite short, usually indicating assent to Socrates' statements and occasionally asking for a clarification, making a comment, or indicating his desire for which direction the argument should take. Almost all of the substance of the ideas was spoken by Socrates, but he continually checked at each step that the answerer was in agreement with propositions. The discussion became so stimulating that Theaetetus requested that Socrates go into the question that all things are at rest. However, Socrates surprised Theodorus by not eagerly attacking this question. He decided rather to return to questioning Theaetetus on knowledge since they have set this as their task, and the other subject was too large to discuss in passing.114

The first book of the Republic shows Socrates asking questions in his inimitable style. Early on we have an example of Socrates asking open-ended questions rather than his usual leading questions as in an argument or refutation. He wished to learn from those older, and he asked Cephalus about his experience. Here he was not looking for assent or a particular response, but he wanted to know if the gentleman found old age hard to bear. Pleased with the value of the response, Socrates decided to draw him out by asking if his happiness was due to his wealth. Then he asked him what he felt had been the greatest benefit he had gotten from his wealth-again a personal question not calling for only one universally right answer. Cephalus felt that wealth was best for a person who lives in justice and piety. At this point Socrates shifted the discussion from Cephalus' personal experience to a search for a definition of what justice is. The classical definition of Simonides that justice is "paying back what is due" was refuted by Socrates by means of a couple of exceptional cases. Cephalus easily agreed, apparently having no taste for argument. Polemarchus did not agree and took over the argument as Cephalus left.115 By asking Polemarchus short questions and gaining his assent Socrates was able to get him to concur in the refutation of Simonides' proposition.

At this point the sophist Thrasymachus had gotten very upset and blasted Socrates for his folly and demanded that he answer instead of ask questions and declare what his definition of justice is. When Socrates admitted that he could not, Thrasymachus accused him of getting out of it by using his typical irony. Now Thrasymachus had asked for an answer which did not mention duty or advantage or profit or gain or interest, and Socrates complained that this was an unfair request to prohibit what might be the true answers. Socrates asked how could he answer when he knew nothing; but since Thrasymachus professed to know, he should tell the others what he knew. Therefore Thrasymachus gave his definition of justice, and Socrates questioned him on it. After Socrates had refuted Thrasymachus' conception by means of the example of artists and rulers who do what is in the interest of those whom they serve, Thrasymachus took another tack by making a long speech. He then wanted to leave, but Socrates and the others urged him to stay so that these ideas he had just expressed could be tested. Socrates indicated that Thrasymachus must not care whether their lives were better or worse from not understanding his points; they requested that he stay and share his knowledge with them.116 In this way Socrates was able to keep the discussion going, and eventually through his cross-examination technique he refuted all of the points that Thrasymachus was able to offer. Again he used the analogy of the arts, and he also showed that complete injustice is chaotic and destructive by showing what would happen if justice and cooperation were completely absent. At the conclusion of the argument Socrates still felt that he knew nothing about what justice actually is, but at least Thrasymachus had become calm and was no longer angry.117

Xenophon also showed us Socrates asking questions. In his Symposium Socrates humorously demonstrated his value as a procurer by asking if the eyes, voice, and words could not create either friendliness or animosity. Also does not the procurer make people attractive, not only to one but to many? Each of Socrates' questions was answered quite simply by "Certainly."118 Here is another example of Socrates merely gaining assent by his questions. A little later in the beauty contest, Socrates and Critobulus exchange questions and answers as they compared their features. The questions of Critobulus were simply asking for information, while those of Socrates were asking for agreement on the point he was making about the different features being beautiful because they are functional. Socrates won the argument but lost the contest.119

In Plato's Alcibiades I Socrates declared that he did not have the gift of making long speeches; but if Alcibiades was willing to answer his questions, he would show him his need for education. Socrates then began the step-by-step questioning which was designed to demonstrate to Alcibiades that his ambitions and beliefs were not supported by knowledge.120 Socrates got Alcibiades to see that he probably did not know the difference between justice and injustice. Alcibiades once prefaced his reply with the words: "By what you say." Socrates therefore labored to show him that he, Alcibiades, was the one actually making the statements because he was answering and Socrates was only asking. Alcibiades agreed that he would more likely be persuaded by answering and saying "the case is so," than he would be if Socrates were making the statements.121 This is a simple but important key to the Socratic method. Socrates did not preach to the listener or attempt to impose his will on one. By asking questions, however leading they were, he left it open to the other person to exercise one's own will freely by choosing to agree or not. Thus it became difficult for the person to deny the conclusions since he has agreed to each step of the process. Of course Socrates had to have the ability to adapt to whatever response the person made.

In the Greater Hippias Socrates cross-examined the famous sophist on the idea of beauty. This is the subject upon which Hippias had been discoursing to many of the young men. Since he claimed to know what beauty is, Socrates was most eager to find out also by questioning him. Hippias gave examples of beautiful things, but Socrates was looking for the essence or definition of beauty itself. Each answer that Hippias gave, Socrates was able to show to be insufficient or unnecessary to cases of beauty. Finally Socrates suggested they consider a more universal concept such as "the appropriate." This was shown to give only the appearance of beauty. Under the examination Hippias felt confused but declared that if he could meditate alone on it he knew he could find it with perfect accuracy. However, Socrates wanted him to discover it in his presence, so he kept asking him questions. After the refutations had exhausted Hippias' ideas, Socrates began to offer suggestions; the questions became even more leading and the answers shorter. However, even Socrates' own ideas were not able to stand alone as definitions of beauty under his cross-examination. No matter how close each concept came to the beautiful, Socrates found some difference; and since it was somehow different, it could not be the same. Or again he brought up cases to show that X is not always in every way beautiful.122 The continually destructive character of these refutations had perhaps led some to question the authenticity of this dialog. The method of argument was very Socratic even though the intent seemed more sophistical than the ultimate positivity or quest for what is truly beneficial to the person which usually characterized Socrates' searching.

Plato in the Protagoras showed us Socrates meeting with the greatest of the sophists. He asked Protagoras the open-ended question of whether virtue could be taught, and allowed him to respond in the form of a fable.123 After the speech Socrates requested that he be allowed to ask some questions concerning the points of Protagoras. He had often noticed that some public speakers were like books in that they were not able to answer questions about what they said. However, Protagoras could do both; so he proceeded to question him.124 As Socrates began to pin down the great master, Protagoras went off into a lengthy answer to explain his point and was cheered by the listeners. Socrates, however, ironically claimed to have a bad memory, and requested that Protagoras keep his answers short. When Protagoras refused, Socrates indicated his reluctance to alter his method at this point and was going to leave. Before going, however, Socrates made it clear that he was not good at long speeches, and since Protagoras claimed to be able to do both, he ought to adapt to Socrates' style. Finally they agreed, and Socrates offered to answer or ask the questions. When Protagoras questioned him on a point from a poem, Socrates demonstrated his ability to answer as well as ask the questions. Socrates was not fooled by the apparent contradiction and was able to elucidate the difference. He also went on to explain his interpretation of the poem by Pittacus and its relation to the work of Simonides.125

We find Socrates again requesting short answers from another eminent sophist in the Gorgias. Gorgias was famous as a rhetorician, and it was on the subject of rhetoric that Socrates cross-examined him. Knowing his tendency to make speeches, Socrates asked him if he was willing to keep his answers short. As they proceeded, Socrates said he was pleased with the brevity of Gorgias' answers. He also indicated that he was very careful not to take for granted what the answers of the other person would be; but he always waited for the response and occasionally repeated a simple question, not to gain a contradiction, but so that the argument could move consecutively. He did not wish to get into a habit of anticipating the other's thoughts, but he preferred that the person develop one's own views in one's own way, whatever they may be.126 This openness in Socrates was also important and was sometimes overlooked, perhaps because the written texts do not change like live situations.

When Socrates observed that there were contradictions in what Gorgias was saying about rhetoric, he checked with the man to see if he, like Socrates, really was willing and happy to be refuted if he happened to be in error, because he did not want to arouse any personal hostility or jealousy. After Gorgias agreed, Socrates showed the inconsistency that rhetoric can be used rightly or wrongly and yet was also a science of right and wrong. Gorgias did not react to this, but Polus became quite upset. Therefore Socrates continued the discussion with him.127 Finally Socrates ran up against the challenge of Callicles and praised him for his knowledge, good-will, and outspokenness, since these would enable them to have an intelligent, good, and effective discussion. At the same time Socrates expressed his ironic modesty as he indicated that any error he made was due to ignorance. When Callicles said that Socrates was being ironic, he did not agree and referred to Callicles' description of him as taking philosophy too far.128 For Socrates his position of modesty was an honest one, though this view was not shared by others.

Also in the Gorgias Socrates showed his ability to answer questions and give substantive ideas. When Polus chose to ask rather than answer, he asked Socrates the same question he had been examining Gorgias on: what is rhetoric? Socrates categorized it as an experience of flattery rather than art, and went on to show its relationship to other flatteries and analogous arts. Socrates explained that it is a mere flattery rather than an art because it does not contain the knowledge of the good as justice does. Socrates apologized for making a lengthy explanation, but it was rather clear who was in control of the discussion because of greater knowledge and insight. Although Polus was the one asking the questions, he did not have the Socratic skill.129

Socrates was usually much more careful about the statements he made than were the people with whom he talked. He focused on the truth, as when Polus asked him what kind of an art rhetoric is, he replied, "To say the truth, Polus, it is not an art at all, in my opinion."130 An unwatchful person might have just answered what type before checking to see whether it is in fact an art. In the Euthyphro we find another small indication of this carefulness. In clarifying what Euthyphro's definition of holiness is, Euthyphro agreed, but he added the phrase, "If you like to call it so." Socrates replied, "I do not like to call it so, if it is not true."131 Socrates admitted that the questioner must follow the answerer, but he did not have to agree that what he said is true.

Sometimes Socrates distinguished the precise aspects of a certain case in order to clarify an ambiguity. When Alcibiades held that some noble things are bad such as when men rescue their friends in battle but are killed or wounded. He showed through questioning that the noble courage is good, but the resulting carnage is bad. The event is complex rather than simple and has good in it because of the courage and bad in it because of the result; but that does not make the noble itself bad.132

In the Euthydemus Socrates' method of questioning was contrasted to the sophistical tricks of two neophytes in argument. Euthydemus and Dionysodorus played with the young Cleinias by refuting him whether he took either side of a question. Concerned about his young friend, Socrates explained how they did this by equivocating on two different meanings of the same word. He counseled that these tricks are a sporting game but they do not lead to wisdom.133 After some more of the verbal juggling, Socrates entreated the two men to display some serious reasoning. To further encourage them he gave them another example. (He had already demonstrated an argument exhorting people toward wisdom.) In this argument Socrates continued to pursue the theme that knowledge should be useful.134 In this dialog Plato seemed to be endeavoring to show that the method of Socrates sought positive values and was not to be confused with the sophistry of his imitators. When Euthydemus and his brother tried to play their game on Socrates, he found himself attempting to clarify the meaning of their questions or the corresponding meaning of his answers in order to avoid getting into ambiguities. However, they complained when he did not fall into their traps. He finally agreed to submit to their game, but the value of the results was rather ridiculous.135
Although Socrates did not claim to be skilled at making speeches, he would occasionally give an extended discourse. In the Phaedrus he considered himself an amateur speaker, but he finally yielded to this friend's request for a rhetorical display. Socrates found the theme that the non-lover is better than the lover for the beloved to be a repugnant idea, and he was so embarrassed that he covered his head in shame.136 Later he redeemed himself by discoursing on the madness of love and its benefits. In the Protagoras after he claimed that he was not good at long speeches, Socrates gave a lengthy interpretation of the poems by Simonides and Pittacus.137 Socrates' humility about making speeches may have merely indicated a preference for the discussion method. There are many examples of different kinds of speeches that he gave. In the Theaetetus we see Socrates mocking up a speech for the late Protagoras in which he pretended to talk to Socrates and the others.138 In the Menexenus we even find him giving a patriotic oration which he said he learned from Aspasia, the mistress of Pericles.139 However, since the speech surveyed the history of Athens down to 386 BC, thirteen years after Socrates' death, the authenticity of the dialog is obviously suspect. In the next section we will examine other speeches of Socrates which utilize particular styles such as myth, allegory, etc.

Socrates was also eager to hear the speeches of others as in the Phaedrus where he allowed the young man to manipulate him just so that he could hear the speech of Lysias. In the Timaeus, which is supposed to be on the day after the discussion in the Republic, Socrates welcomed a discourse from Timaeus, Critias, and Hermocrates.140 In this dialog Timaeus gave a very long lecture on cosmology, and in the Critias Socrates granted his friend by that name indulgence to trace the history of Atlantis.141 The text of his account broke off in the middle, and there is no record of a speech by Hermocrates.
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 112 发表于: 2009-03-15
SOCRATES
Style and Methods
(Continued)
Poetry and Metaphor
Discussion
This chapter has been published in the book CONFUCIUS AND SOCRATES Teaching Wisdom. For ordering information, please click here.

Poetry and Metaphor
Socrates used more than pure reasoning to get his points across. He often quoted or interpreted poetry to illustrate a particular idea. He also used analogies extensively, and occasionally he would develop an allegory or recount a tale which was appropriate to his theme. Socrates was very familiar with the myths, fables, history, poetry, and plays of his culture. However, in his discussions he did not really examine these for their own sake, but he referred to them for the benefit they might add to the listeners. Xenophon recalled Socrates saying, "And the treasures that the wise men of old have left us in their written books I open and explore with my friends. If we see something good, we extract it and believe it is a great gain to be useful to one another."142

Xenophon in his defense of Socrates against certain accusers, labored to show that Socrates' interpretation of certain lines of poetry was not as his detractors had imagined.143 In persuading Aristippus that the easy and pleasant life is not always the best, Xenophon had Socrates quote a similar passage from Hesiod that Plato had him use in the Protagoras about the road to virtue being a steep, hard climb, though it is easy on top.144 He then quoted Epicharmus twice on a similar theme.

Xenophon also recorded an incident when Socrates was talking with a man who had been chosen general. He quoted Homer about Agamemnon being "shepherd of the people" and that a good general is a good king. Since a good king makes his subjects happy, his duty ought to be to make the people happy.145

Both Xenophon and Plato had Socrates quote the same lines from Theognis about good people teaching each other, while company with the bad is corrupting.146 In the Meno Socrates quoted another passage from the same poet which contradicted the idea that virtue could be taught. The implication is that poetry can be used to illustrate an argument but not to settle one.

In the Protagoras when this sophist questioned Socrates he based his arguments on phrases from the poets Simonides and Pittacus. Socrates through his ability to interpret their precise meanings brought out a deeper understanding of the poems. However, at the conclusion of this detailed literary critique, he indicated his preference for direct discussion between the participants compared to having poetry as a kind of entertainment like flute-girls or dancing girls. The poets were not there to declare what they meant in specific passages, and therefore each person could only offer one's interpretation. However, true gentlemen can put poetry aside and discuss in their own persons, testing the truth and themselves more directly.147

How poetry is somewhat removed from wisdom and self-knowledge is indicated in Plato's Ion. Ion was a man who had become accomplished at reciting the poems of Homer, and therefore claimed to know about everything which was mentioned by Homer. Socrates used his usual method of questioning, but he also demonstrated the ability to call forth appropriate lines from the great poet in order to communicate with Ion who did not seem to care about anything else. Although Ion had memorized all of Homer and could portray his work admirably, it became apparent through Socrates' questioning that this did not make him wise in these subjects as he had thought.148

Praising Socrates in Plato's Symposium Alcibiades described how he was able to use words so as to reveal an inner meaning. The words, like the physical appearance of Socrates which resembled Silenus or a satyr, might seem common and ordinary, but just as a statue of a satyr might open to reveal a god within it, the words of Socrates also held a deep understanding extending to the entire duty of the good and noble person.149

Let us look at how Socrates clothed his ideas in everyday language by examining next his use of analogies.In the Charmides when Critias said that temperance is a science of itself, Socrates compared it to other sciences such as medicine which produces health and architecture which produces buildings so that he could ask him what results come from wisdom or temperance.150

To describe the inspiration and influence of poetry in the Ion Socrates used the analogy of a magnet and a series of rings attracted to it. God is the source of the inspiration for the poet who through his inspirational output attracts a rhapsode to recite the poetry; this expression in turn has a magnetic appeal to the audience. In the figure, God is the magnet, and the poet, rhapsode, and the audience are the respective metal rings attached to the magnet.151 Such a picture could convey the overall relationships of the situation in a holistic manner.

In the Cratylus Socrates used the analogy of the arts to show that the proper tool must be used in a correct way. He started with the natural processes of cutting and burning, then moved on to speaking, weaving, carpentry, and the legislator. The user of each thing knows it best, and it is the dialectician who can ask and answer questions who knows words best.152 By showing the relationships in the simple arts, Socrates could lead people from what they knew to see the relationships in areas which they did not yet know.

Socrates employed many analogies in the Republic. He asked what good thing justice gives as medicine gives drugs and diet and as cookery gives seasoning. The physician helps the sick; the pilot guides a ship in rough seas. How does the just person help? Polemarchus replied that it is in war that he could harm his enemy and help his friends. Justice might also be useful in time of peace, as farming and shoemaking. Polemarchus suggested contracts, and Socrates asked about brick-layers and harp-players to discover that he meant money partnerships. Socrates got Polemarchus to agree that anyone who has knowledge of using things such as the horseman for horses and the pilot for ships is better in these areas than the just person. Polemarchus got in the position of saying that justice is only useful when these things are useless. Also since Polemarchus had left out any concept of right and wrong, by the analogies that a good guard can most easily sneak off and a good keeper most easily steal, Socrates showed that justice is a thief!153 Here we see that the use of analogies and examples in no way guaranteed a good argument. Rather they are more of a pedagogical tool which enables one to look at relationships of things that may already be familiar.

To refute Thrasymachus' notion that the ruler does things for his own advantage, Socrates used the analogies of the physician who helps his patients and the captain whose interest is for his sailors.154

Most of the Republic is in fact based on the analogy between the individual and the state, which may allow its greatest danger of misrepresentation, because the members of the social classes are not whole people but represent only part of the psyche. Nevertheless Socrates used this pedagogical tool to blow up justice from its small size in the individual to the larger scope of the state.155 In other words, justice may be easier to understand or learn about if we can see it in its larger scope. Another purpose of this analogy is to compare justice in the state with justice in the individual. He said,

If they agree, we shall be satisfied;
or, if there is a difference in the individual,
we will return again to the state and test the theory.
The friction of the two when rubbed against each other
may possibly strike a light in which justice may shine forth,
and the vision which is then revealed we will fix within us.156

In examining the characteristics of the psyche it is noted, as with the arms of the archer, that there seems to be opposing forces of motivation. Because the logical principle holds that nothing can be and not be at the same time in the same relation, it is likely that there are at least two different aspects of the consciousness. These are held to be desire and reason, and they are illustrated by the story of Leontius, who felt a desire to see some dead bodies lying on the ground after an execution while at the same time he felt an abhorrence to them.157

A good analogy is one which gives the listener a clear and comprehensive picture of the relationships in the situation. The selection and education of the guardians is likened to the dyeing of wool. The ideal is to find the white wool and prepare it so that it will take the purple and hold it fast. Thus the guardians must be of good character so that the laws will make a clear and lasting imprint on them.158

The government was described as a ship with a mutinous crew of politicians, and the skillful pilot is the true philosopher but appears to some as a useless star-gazer. The reason the star-gazer is considered useless is because the other people refuse to make use of his abilities.159

Book VIII of the Republic is a very enlightening analysis of political psychology. Socrates described four forms of government, which can degenerate from the best government of virtue. They are timocracy, oligarchy (or plutocracy), democracy, and tyranny. After each state was described, the analogous human character was portrayed, and the process by which the government degenerated into the next form was shown over the course of a family generation.160 The analogies of the ship and of bees were also utilized. The result of drawing such a comprehensive picture is that the listener can relate it to many aspects of one's experience and on different levels of consciousness.

In the Theaetetus Socrates used the analogy of an aviary with the whole cage representing the mind, and birds indicating various elements of knowledge. There are three stages of possessing the birds: 1) the original capture, 2) maintaining them in the cage, and 3) their recapture for some use. The three stages of knowledge are: 1) the original learning, 2) latent awareness, and 3) conscious use of the knowledge. Wrong opinion is due to catching the wrong bird for the purpose. The analogy may be helpful as far as it goes, but Socrates challenged it by wondering where ignorance comes from if we have knowledge in our mind. How could knowledge cause ignorance? Theaetetus further confused the metaphor by suggesting that some of the birds might be forms of ignorance.161 Alas, the figure may have been helpful in understanding some principles, but it fails to resolve others. In order to understand knowledge as a composite of elements, Socrates suggested the analogy of letters and syllables. However, this analogy did little more than stimulate a discussion of the whole and the parts. The letters were not defined, and the syllables could not be truly known if the letters were not known.162 It seemed that this analogy did not prove to be very useful, because it did not really show any meaningful relationships or a pattern familiar to our experience.

Also in this dialog the metaphor of a wax tablet was used to represent memory as the impressions made by perception. These impressions are then recalled suitably or not in relation to perceptions later on. The quality of one's memory is indicated by the nature of the wax-whether it is clean or muddy, too hard to make a deep imprint or too soft to hold the pattern.163 This metaphor seems to be appropriate for memory, but it is hard to relate it to other aspects of knowledge.

In the Philebus Socrates used the analogy of letters to show the intermediate steps between one and infinity which it is the task of dialectic to show. The sound of the voice is one and yet infinite, but as the child learns the letters, as they were first invented by the Egyptian god Theuth, he learns the art of speech. The knowledge of the number and nature of these sounds makes one a grammarian.164 In this case the subject is more abstract and the use of letters and the experience of learning them is more appropriate and meaningful.

In discussing how false opinions can develop, Socrates described the soul or consciousness as a book where memory and perception write down words, sometimes falsely. In addition to the scribe there is an artist who paints images in the soul, and the images may also be true or false. This image-painting, especially of future hopes, is often related to pleasures which may be good or bad. Socrates associated the good pleasures with true images and the bad pleasures with false images.165 This analogy appears to work because of the close relationship between the imagination and the desire for pleasure which most people probably experience visually. Also it is interesting to note the characteristic Socratic unification of the true with the good and the false with the bad.

One of the most frequent analogies Socrates used was to examine something on the level of the soul or consciousness as compared to the level of the body or the physical. This is used several times in the Gorgias. The most comprehensive series of relationships is designed to show how rhetoric as a flattery rather than an art of consciousness corresponds to other arts and flatteries of the consciousness and the body. There are also two arts and their two shams each for soul and body, one which institutes and the other which corrects. The physical arts and their flatteries are as follows: gymnastics is to beautification (cosmetics, clothing) as medicine is to cookery. The consciousness arts are: legislation is to sophistry as justice is to rhetoric. The complete geometric ratios are: gymnastic is to beautification as legislation is to sophistry, and as medicine is to cookery, justice is to rhetoric.166 This can give us a comprehension of many relationships in a short space; it is easy to remember because it all fits together in a pattern.

Later on Socrates compared bodily disease and the need for medicine with vice, the disease of the soul, and the need for justice.167 This helps those who have difficulty seeing the soul level to recognize the relationship on the physical level. Once the relationship is understood, only the level needs to be transferred. Finally in the discussion with Callicles, Socrates indicated that the disease of the body is treated by temperance, and vices of the soul are cured by self-control and the chastisements of justice.168 By means of the physical analogies Socrates was able to get Callicles to see this.

Socrates would often tell a story or use an allegorical figure to express comprehensive and deep meanings. In the Gorgias to show Callicles the value of temperance Socrates recounted the tale of an Italian that the soul is a vessel, and the ignorant or uninitiated have holes that leak where the desires are because of intemperance and incontinence. The temperate person may have equal difficulty filling one's containers with wine, honey, and milk; but because they remain full one is not bothered by them, while those that are leaky are continually striving to fill them by painful struggle.169 By this metaphor Socrates was able to indicate the dissipation of energy and perpetual stress caused by lack of self-discipline over one's desires.

Socrates often got these allegories from other people and then applied them in an appropriate situation. Xenophon recorded his using a tale from Prodicus' essay "On Heracles" to show Aristippus the dangers of a life of pleasure and the value of duty. The story presented the young Heracles at a crossroads where he must decide whether to pursue a life of virtue or vice, which are personified as women. Virtue is fair, temperate, of high-bearing, pure, and modest in her manner and dress, while Vice is plump, soft, sensual, and looking for attention. Vice runs up to meet Heracles first and promises him all sorts of delights and pleasures without any work. Her friends call her Happiness, but those who hate her have nicknamed her Vice. Virtue tells Heracles he must work for the truly good things by benefiting his friends and taking care of things. When Vice says that her road is shorter, Virtue criticizes her for being always unsatisfied by her pleasures and for leading to an old age of weakness and misery. The virtuous enjoy simple food, do their duties, sleep well, are content and respected even in old age. By this story Socrates presented Aristippus with clear choices to consider in regard to the life that he would lead.170

In the Philebus Socrates personified the pleasures and wisdom, and then he asked them questions. The pleasures would like to live with wisdom; but wisdom is only willing to dwell with the more pure pleasures because the heavier pleasures hinder wisdom by carelessness and forgetfulness.171 Also in the Crito Socrates personified the laws of the state so that he could carry on a discussion with them.172 This technique enabled Socrates to get deeply into an abstract subject in such a way as could be closely related to human experience and have a personal appeal to the listener.

Socrates used natural metaphors as in the Phaedo where he interpreted the song of the swans before they die as prophetic rejoicing in expectation of the blessings in the other world.173 In the Republic Socrates referred to their search for justice as hunters following along its trail.174 Again this would enable his listeners to be more interested because of the picture in their minds which recalled some familiar experience.

In the Republic we find Socrates using several allegories to explain and describe complex relationships. In Book VI Socrates was attempting to convey the idea of the good, but he discovered he could not do it adequately. Therefore he offered to give a representation of the child of the good even though he warned them the description could not help but be false to the reality of what they were talking about. He described sight as dependent on the eyes, color, and the light which comes from the good in the visible world; what the sun is in the visible world, the good is in the intellectual world. Just as the sun generates light, the good creates truth and knowledge. Then Socrates showed more detailed relationships again by means of geometrical proportions or ratios. In the visible world there is the reflection of images and shadows as compared to actual physical things which we perceive. In the intellectual world what corresponds to the images and shadows are the hypotheses, and above them are the actual ideas. Geometry is an example of using hypotheses, and dialectic is the process concerned with the ideas themselves as first principles. Each of the four levels has the corresponding faculty of the soul which engages in those activities. The ideas are the domain of the pure intellect and knowing. Hypotheses are dealt with by understanding and thinking. Our higher relation to the visible world is one of belief, and the lower is that of image-making or conjecture.175 This design shows the relationships in a very intellectual and abstract way without feeling tone or much to hold on to from personal experience.

Therefore Socrates followed it up with the allegory of the cave which uses the sun again and attempts to give a higher perspective on the human condition. To indicate how the good itself is really better, human experience must be portrayed worse than it is so that a better level can be shown which people can grasp. Socrates used a similar device in the Phaedo when he said that this world is as murky as being in the ocean compared to the clarity of the other world which would be like air, except that our world is of air and the other even clearer.176 In the cave people are chained in darkness and can only see the shadows of a fire cast on a wall of the cave. Most of the prisoners cannot even turn their heads to see those who are carrying the objects by the fire which make the shadows on the wall. To the prisoners the shadows are the only reality. When a prisoner is liberated he needs time to adjust to moving his body and seeing the light of the fire directly. He has difficulty persuading the other prisoners that there is a higher reality, and he begins to lose interest in the shadows which are their whole world. Gradually he will be able to accustom his eyes to the light of the fire as he climbs the rugged ascent out of the cave. First he sees shadows best, then objects themselves; he gazes at the moon and stars, and finally he is able to behold the sun in the light of day, seeing everything in its proper place. When he returns to the cave, he has compassion for his fellow prisoners but does not care about their contests and honors; his eyes are not used to the darkness, and he appears ridiculous to them. They feel threatened by anyone who would try to free a prisoner and lead him up to the light; and therefore if they caught him, they would put him to death.177

Having presented the allegory, Socrates explained how it fits with the worlds of the visible and the intellectual, and his analogy of the sun to the idea of the good. The cave represents the visible world and the fire the physical sun. This indicates how he has lowered it a level in order to show two levels with a higher one than is usually recognized. The journey out of the cave represents the ascent of the soul into the intellectual world which is culminated with the idea of the good (sun outside the cave). This good is the source of reason and truth and the essential guide for all human life. It explains why those who have had the beatific vision are reluctant to become involved in human affairs and the difficulties they have in dealing with the shadows of justice as conceived by those who have never seen absolute justice itself. It is more appropriate to laugh at the one who is adjusting his eyes to the light, for this is a joyful occurrence, rather than to laugh at the one who has returned to the cave. Education does not consist of putting knowledge into the soul, like sight into blind eyes, because the soul already has the ability to learn. Education should be the process of liberating the prisoner's whole being from the chains and turning one by degrees toward the light of the good. The future leaders must turn away from sensual pleasures and seek the knowledge of the good; after they have seen the light, they ought to return to the cave to serve the state and take up the duties of philosophers. Their experience with the good will enable them to transcend any concerns of honors, wealth, ambition, or jealousy.178 By the comprehensiveness of this allegory and its interpretation, Socrates was able to tie many things together concerning human experience in this world and how the process of transcendence can be approached.

In Book IX of the Republic Socrates gave a three-part image of the soul to represent different aspects of human consciousness. The appetites are symbolized by a many-headed monster or beast, the aggressive instinct by a lion, and reason by a person. These three creatures appear on the outside as a single human to those who are not able to look within. Injustice in the individual is to allow the beast to feast and strengthen the lion while starving and weakening the person. Justice is giving the person control and mastery over the creature so that the beast is tamed and made gentle, and the lion-heart becomes one's ally. Then Socrates used this comparison to explain how justice, when the divine element in people rules over the bestial, is far superior to the intemperate wildness of the beast. People are blamed when they allow the lower nature to control them. Letting the divine wisdom rule is generally considered best, and it is better for the other levels to serve. Also children are ruled by adults until the ruling principle is established within them with a guardian in their heart. These are evidences of the value of justice, temperance, and wisdom.179 These vivid images and the analogous experiences, which show how these elements interact, enable the listener to comprehend the three levels of this psychology and its application.

In the Phaedrus Socrates gave an inspired speech on love as a madness. He described the soul and its travels with the image of two winged horses and a charioteer flying through various realms of heaven. One horse is noble and the other ignoble, and the driving of them is not easy. The souls that lose their wings, fall to earth and taking up a body become a living creature; it is the soul which moves the body. The souls that travel with the gods perceive the true essence of justice, temperance, and absolute knowledge. The wings of the soul are nourished on the truth found in the higher realms, but those that cannot control the horses fall into a human body on earth, where they reincarnate until the wings are grown again. Philosophers can grow these wings more quickly than others. Learning is a process of recalling or recognizing in earthly experience the images of beauty, temperance, and justice which were seen directly in the heavenly realms of true being. Many souls have forgotten the holy things they have seen, but beauty and love tend to re-awaken these divine qualities. As the beauty of the beloved vitalizes the love, the wings begin to grow. Souls are differentiated by the characteristics of the gods they follow. Socrates described the good and virtuous horse as compared to the bad, vicious one. The beauty of the beloved inspires the white horse to adoration as true beauty is recalled, while the dark horse is filled with desire and urges the chariot toward sensual indulgence. As the charioteer exercises temperance and goodwill, then:

Love overflows upon the lover,
and some enters into one's soul,
and some when one is filled flows out again;
and as a breeze or an echo rebounds from the smooth rocks
and returns whence it came,
so does the stream of beauty passing through the eyes
which are the windows of the soul,
come back to the beautiful one;
there arriving and animating the passages of the wings,
watering them and making them grow,
and filling the soul of the beloved also with love.180

One loves but does not understand it, and the lover is one's mirror to see oneself. Their love from this point on depends on their self-control whether they will give in to the desires of the dark steed or begin the heavenly pilgrimage through philosophy.181 Here Socrates has presented another image to portray the heavenly in relation to the earthly and to describe love and two possible choices of how to experience its inspiration.
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 113 发表于: 2009-03-15
In Plato's Symposium Socrates related the teachings he heard from Diotima on love. To describe Love as an intermediary between the divine and the mortal, and as a mean between opposites such as ignorance and wisdom, she used an allegory of the birth of Love. The story goes that at a feast in heaven on the birthday of Aphrodite, Poverty contrived to lay with Plenty, who is the son of Discretion. The child conceived was Love, who shares the qualities of being poor and always in need with the resourcefulness of a strong and enterprising hunter. Love is what unites the mortal and immortal, pursues wisdom, and is always flowing in and out.182 Here Socrates used the personification of opposites in order to show love as a dynamic quality which bridges opposites as a mean.

In Xenophon's Symposium, Socrates also referred to figures from myth to show the spiritual connection between gods and humans through love. He pointed out that Zeus loved many mortals, but it was only those he loved for their souls' sake that he carried up to heaven, such as Ganymede.183 Here again Socrates was implying the significant difference between divine love and mortal passion.

Phaedrus once accused Socrates of making up stories from whatever country he pleased. This was after Socrates told an Egyptian story of how the god Thamus (Ammon) commented upon the dangers of Theuth's invention of written letters. Memories will be weakened, and people will have the appearance of wisdom, thinking they know more than they do.184 Socrates used this story to warn Phaedrus of the dangers and limitations of the written word.

In the Charmides Socrates told how he got his charm cure from a Thracian physician of the divine king Zalmoxis which can even make a human immortal, but one must not use it on a part of the body until the whole of the soul is treated.185 In this way Socrates implied the precedence of the spiritual work prior to the physical, and it enabled him to move the focus of the discussion from Charmides' headache to an investigation of temperance.

In the Gorgias Socrates concluded his argument on justice by relating the Greek myth of the judgment which follows after death. He suspected that Callicles would only look upon it as a fable, but Socrates believed that it is true. He started with the Homeric account of how the empire was divided between Zeus, Poseidon, and Pluto, and how since the days of Kronos those who lived in justice and holiness have passed over after death to the Islands of the Blessed. The unjust and impious go to Tartarus for punishment. Socrates showed the problem of judging by worldly standards by having Pluto complain that the judgments according to apparel, physical appearance, wealth, and rank have not been accurate. Therefore Zeus decided that Prometheus should take away the foreknowledge of death, and they should be stripped naked to the soul before they are judged-both those who are judged and the judges. The judges were to be the sons of Zeus: Minos, Rhadamanthus, and Aeacus.
Then Socrates interpreted the myth. Death is nothing else but a separation of the soul from the body. Just as bodies tend to maintain their habits and qualities, so too does the soul exhibit its character and former actions. When the soul presents itself before the judge, there is no indication of its social station on earth; even a king may only be seen as a cruel and wicked criminal, insolent and licentious. In fact a position of power tends to corrupt the soul more often than not, while it is often the humble and private citizen who may be a philosopher and go to the Islands of the Blessed. Finally Socrates concluded that these things are true as far as he is concerned, and therefore he strove to live as best he could so that he could present his soul pure and undefiled before the judge after death. He also exhorted Callicles to be just in this life in preparation for what would inevitably come.186 Again Socrates had to use myth and allegory to attempt to convey what pertains to the soul, because these are the areas of life which are invisible to physical perception. Also he presented the listener with a definite choice of alternatives.

A similar account is found in the tale of Er at the conclusion of the Republic. This story was presented as an actual experience of a man who died in battle, had his soul leave his body to go on a long journey before he returned to his body and came alive again twelve days later. Here again the description of the other world appears symbolic and mythical. He first found himself at the place of judgment between two openings from the lower world and two openings in the upper heaven. The unjust were bound and taken down below, and the just ascended the heavenly way. Souls also came from these places, some dusty and worn, the others clean and bright. All actions from earthly life were balanced out by punishments or rewards; Er witnessed several cases of each. Then he and the souls that had returned from the other worlds went to a place with a great column of light with bright and pure colors. They saw the spindle of Necessity and the revolutions of the planets with their corresponding musical sounds. The three Fates of the past, present, and future accompanied their harmony. Each soul was to choose their guiding spirit or divinity for their next life on earth. The various destinies were very complex, and Socrates reminded his listeners at this point of the great value of wisdom in discerning good from evil. Er then saw the choices made by various famous heroes. When the selections were made, the genius or divinity led the souls to the Fates to ratify their destiny. Then they marched to the scorching plain of Oblivion where they drank varying amounts from the river of Forgetfulness, except Er who was prevented from drinking. From there they went to their births, and Er returned to his body with the ability to remember what had happened.

After the tale, Socrates briefly exhorted his friends toward the heavenly way of justice and virtue, remembering that the soul is immortal.187 By means of this tale, Socrates explained the ultimate balancing action of divine justice, showed that individual human destinies are not random but freely chosen, indicated what kind of things might happen to the eternal soul before, in between, and after lives on earth, and symbolically portrayed why people do not remember what they have done in the other world or before birth. Such an account may assist souls in recognizing or intuiting the experiences they have had but do not remember.

Discussion
Socrates was a master at handling a discussion, and in addition to his way of asking questions and using metaphors and stories, he also would point out examples, analyze concepts, search for definitions, lead by dialectical agreement, and summarize the main points.

In Xenophon's Symposium Socrates used various kinds of examples to support an idea. Even a girl who did somersaults and gymnastic tricks through hoops of swords became for Socrates evidence that courage could be taught.188 In further encouraging Callias to a more spiritual rather than carnal love, Socrates moved from the mythic example of Zeus and Ganymede to other heroes and then to the customs of the Thebans, Eleans, and Lacedaemonians in their lovers' relations in battle situations, and finally to the noble gifts Themistocles, Pericles, and Solon gave to Athens.189 Socrates often compared the practices of other people when it was appropriate to the topic to show real possibilities.
In order to refute an argument or a definition, Socrates would often cite cases which were appropriate but contradictory to the previous statement. When Charmides said that temperance is a kind of quietness implying slowness or caution, Socrates brought up many actions such as writing, reading, playing the lyre, wrestling, boxing, running and jumping which are better done quickly rather than slowly. By a couple more questions Socrates made it clear to Charmides that quietness could not be temperance. Then Charmides suggested modesty, but Socrates cited Homer to say that modesty is not good for a needy person, but obviously temperance is good.190 Socrates always seemed to be able to think of cases or examples which could challenge a particular definition or viewpoint.
In the Ion the rhapsode thought he knew Homer so well that he could even be a good general except that the Athenians would not pick him because he was an Ephesian. Socrates was quick to point out actual cases where the Athenians had selected foreigners to be their generals.191 In this way Socrates tested and challenged the statements of others so that the discussion could proceed as accurately as possible.

In analyzing a situation Socrates might also offer constructive criticism. Again in Xenophon's Symposium after the dancing girls had performed with the swords, Socrates recognized that it was dangerous; but he felt that such feats were not appropriate at a banquet. He was more interested in such questions as why a flame gives light while a bronze mirror only reflects it or why olive oil burns. Finally he suggested to the dancers that if they portrayed the Graces or Seasons or the Nymphs in their dance to a flute accompaniment they might get less worn out and the banquet would be enhanced.192 Although Socrates could be critical, he also gave positive suggestions.

At the beginning of the Politician Socrates pointed out to Theodorus, the geometrician, the different values of the sophist, politician, and philosopher by humorously referring to mathematical proportions.193 This brief comment gives some perspective on the relative weight of the entire discussion.

In questioning Theaetetus on knowledge Socrates tested the ideas of Protagoras that knowledge is perception and that "Man is the measure of all things." Socrates showed that knowledge can and must be more than sense perception as in the example of memory. If whatever anyone thought was right, there would be no purpose at all in philosophical discussion, and the ideas of Protagoras would not be worth any more than anyone else's.194 By showing these contradictions Socrates got the other person to clarify his ideas and consider other possibilities.

In the Phaedrus Socrates analyzed the speech of Lysias and then analyzed his own speech. He said that Lysias should have defined love which he never did. Also his speech had no organization; it began with the conclusion and then rambled around. In Socrates' own speech he started with madness, explaining it was caused by human infirmity or divine release of the soul. He then described the four kinds of divine madness as prophecy, initiation, poetry, and love. Socrates employed two principles in his speech: first, a definition unifying the idea of love, and second, dividing it into appropriate species, symbolized here by the two horses. These two principles of the one and the many are the tools of the dialectician who attempts to clarify meaning rather than of the rhetorician who strives only to persuade.195 Such analysis sheds added light on the speeches made and gives a greater understanding of speech-making itself.

Socrates was aware of how easy it is to fall into verbal contradictions, but he knew it was important to distinguish whether the verbal opposition really made a difference to the argument. A good example of this is found in the Republic when he was accused of treating men and women the same when their natures are obviously different. He held that the major difference between the sexes, which is the ability to have babies or not, is no reason for not giving women the same education as men. Women are just as capable as men in taking up the various pursuits in the state except that women tend to be a little weaker physically. In the various abilities there are degrees of difference among all people, men and women. Therefore the government of the state should be in the hands of the best men and the best women.196 The person who could not make such distinctions was easily refuted and would never get very far in dialectic.

After comparing the different forms of government and types of human character, Socrates went on to show that the philosopher is better off than the lover of honor or the lover of wealth. The philosopher has experienced the pleasures of gain and honor from childhood, but the wealthy and the brave have not necessarily developed their reason and experienced the joys of knowing true being. Thus the philosopher is more comprehensive than the others and must know which pleasures are the best.197 By this analysis Socrates showed the relationship of the concepts to each other and which experience level is included within that of a larger one. Having established these, his conclusion became clear to the listener.

One of Socrates' preoccupations was to attempt to define the concept they were talking about. Xenophon told us that he never gave up considering definitions and analyzing others' responses through his questions. Xenophon gave a sample by narrating a discussion with Euthydemus which goes over piety, justice, wisdom, the good, the beautiful, courage, and government; the discussion shows that most of these are interrelated. Xenophon added that whenever someone debated with him about whether a specific person was wiser or braver, Socrates would go back to the definition in question. Xenophon concluded,

By this process of leading back the argument
even his adversary came to see the truth clearly.
Whenever he himself argued out a question,
he advanced by steps that gained general assent,
holding this to be the only sure method.198

This is the crux of the Socratic method and could be used both to refute the other person's hypothesis and to establish a positive understanding.

After refuting Charmides' notions of temperance, Socrates took on Critias, who likewise was caught in contradictions. Critias attempted to save his definition by making new distinctions. This prompted Socrates to request that he define his terms if he intended to make these various distinctions.199 A clear and useful discussion depends on the accuracy of the communication, and therefore agreeing upon the definitions of the terms is essential.

In the Euthyphro Socrates pursued a definition of piety because the man claimed to be an authority on the subject. However, Socrates ran into the common problem of being given cases or examples of piety (as Hippias had done with beauty) rather than its essential meaning that could be applied to all its manifestations. Euthyphro suggested a couple of definitions, but Socrates showed him the contradictions in each of them. When Euthyphro said that piety is justice, Socrates wanted to know their relationship which turned out to be the part to the whole; piety is a part of justice. Then the part must be explained, which Euthyphro said is "attending on the gods." Then the concept of people attending on the gods must be scrutinized and was eventually shown to be fallacious, for how can humans benefit or help God? Neither do humans really trade with the gods. Euthyphro finally came around to his original assertion which had already been refuted. At this point he became frustrated and hurried away.200 Such an exercise was not conclusive, but it did enable a person to examine several definitions that he thought were true and perhaps to realize that he may need to look deeper and more thoroughly to really understand what had seemed so obvious.

In the Theaetetus Socrates asked the young man for a definition of knowledge or science. However, Theaetetus began to list some of the sciences. Socrates explained that this does not tell us what science itself is. He gave the example of clay which could be defined as moistened earth, though there are several different kinds of clay. He also gave the example of geometry of square roots and cube roots. Thus Socrates had given him a model to follow.201 However, defining knowledge turned out to be a difficult task. Although they spent considerable time on it, they were never really satisfied with the results.

One of the best examples of the Socratic method of education is found in the Meno. Meno wanted to know how virtue could be acquired; but Socrates confessed that he did not know what virtue is, which ought to be the first step in the inquiry. Having heard Gorgias, Meno was confident that he could describe the nature of virtue. He declared what a virtuous man does and how a virtuous woman behaves; but Socrates wanted to know the essence, what every act of virtue has in common. Virtue itself will be the same in men or women, and temperance and justice are more abstract examples of it. To help him see the idea of a universal definition, Socrates gave the example of plane figures and gave a definition that would include all kinds. So Meno suggested that virtue is the desire of the good; but Socrates showed that all people desire what they consider to be good. Virtue must be the ability to attain the good. This could be a good definition, but Socrates tripped him up by showing how some people may desire partial goods, such as gold and silver, and may attain them in unjust ways. Therefore the good must be attained with justice, but justice is one of the virtues. How can we define the whole by means of a part of the whole when we still do not know what the whole is? So Socrates returned to the original question, and Meno realized that he had been thrown into confusion by Socrates' spell.202 This is the early stage of the dialectical process which "makes use of those points which the questioned person acknowledges he knows."203 Socrates had been working in a very individual way with the awareness that Meno had in regard to this subject. The refutation part of the process reduced the other person to the kind of ignorance which Socrates usually admitted from the beginning and which seemed so ironic.

Next Meno asked a very important question,

How will you inquire, Socrates,
into that which you do not know?
What will you put forth as the subject of inquiry?
And if you find what you want,
how will you ever know that
this is the thing which you did not know?204

If these doubts were correct, there would be no such thing as learning, because what is known would already be known, and what is not known could never be known. This obviously goes against human experience, but how, then, did Socrates account for the process of learning? Understanding the Socratic psychology of learning is the key to understanding how the Socratic method of pedagogy works. To explain it Socrates referred to the divine mystery of the eternal soul and its inspirational wisdom. Then he described the process.

The soul, then, as being immortal,
and having been born again many times,
and having seen all things that exist,
both in this world and in the other realms,
there is nothing it has not learned;
so that it is no wonder that it is able to call to mind
what it knew before about virtue and other things.
For as all nature is akin, and the soul has learned all things,
there is no difficulty by recalling one thing-
what people call learning-to discover everything else,
if a person is courageous and does not give up searching;
for all research and learning are wholly recognition.205

The word "recognition" is used here to imply "re-cognition" which is what Socrates was describing and differs from what is usually experienced as memory. What he was saying is that the soul has the unique ability to know anything and everything because it is eternal and has a relationship with everything that exists.

When Meno asked how this could be and sought some proof, Socrates offered to give a demonstration with one of his slave boys who would have had no formal education. Socrates presented him with a fairly difficult problem in geometry: how to make a square twice the area of the original square. Socrates used his usual method of asking questions to discover what the person's ideas were. The notions which were not correct, he showed to be false by his questioning. The boy, then, was first brought to the point of realizing that what he first thought was actually incorrect. The negative refutation was completed, and Socrates began the positive part of the dialectic by asking the boy to recognize the validity of certain propositions he had not yet thought of. By presenting these propositions in a step-by-step manner so that the boy could understand each one of them, he was finally able to grasp and fully understand the solution to the problem. This spontaneous recognition of what is incorrect or correct by closely examining the possible solutions is an example of the boy's recalling to mind what is true. He had no experience with geometry before, but nevertheless he demonstrated his ability to recognize and know the solution to a difficult problem.206 Thus education is not only possible, but through a correctly guided inquiry any person can actually learn to recognize any truth that exists! Also since our beliefs are so often found to be faulty, there is even a greater incentive to question them, to search and inquire so that we might shed our false opinions and discover the real truth of things. No wonder Socrates was so committed to this process of inquiry!

Since they now more fully realized that inquiry is worthwhile, Socrates suggested they search together into the nature of virtue. Meno, however, preferred to examine his original question, which was whether virtue could be taught. Socrates agreed to work on testing this hypothesis even though they had not established what virtue is. What is taught must be a form of knowledge. Virtue is good, and knowledge or wisdom also made everything beneficial. Therefore virtue must be closely related to wisdom. If wisdom is taught, and they agreed that it is, then by this argument virtue must be taught. However, if it can be taught there ought to be teachers of it and cases where they taught someone to be virtuous. This search for a teacher of wisdom proved fruitless, and now it looked as though virtue could not be, or at least had not been, taught. Then Socrates suggested that virtue may not always be based on actual knowledge but in many cases merely is due to right opinion. Since people are virtuous without having learned it, it appears as though virtue comes from divine inspiration as a gift of God; for the virtuous are often called divine or blessed. This is the best conclusion available, but Socrates believed they would never know the certain truth until they inquired into and discovered the actual nature of virtue.207 This gap in the dialectic because of Meno's desire to skip over this question prevented them from gaining the original definition they needed.

This idea of recollecting or recognizing knowledge one already has was also demonstrated in Xenophon's Oikonomikos. Here Socrates was learning about household management and farming from the successful Ischomachus. Socrates was relating how this gentleman assisted him in realizing all the things he knew about farming by simply asking him questions and reinforcing Socrates' correct answers. As Ischomachus asked each specific question, Socrates became aware that he knew the answer.

I really wasn't aware that I understood these things;
and so I have been thinking for some time
whether my knowledge extends to smelting gold,
playing the flute, and painting pictures.
For I have never been taught these things
any more than I have been taught farming;
but I have watched men working at these arts,
just as I have watched them farming.208

This is the ability of the soul to learn simply by giving attention to something. Socrates commented on this method of education that he was experiencing. At first he thought he did not know, but the questioning had artfully revealed to him what he did know.

Of course there is nothing in what you have said
that I don't know, Ischomachus.
But I am again set thinking what can have made me
answer 'No' to the question you put to me a while ago,
when you asked me briefly if I understood planting.
For I thought I would have nothing to say
about the right method of planting.
But now that you have undertaken to question me
in particular, my answers, you tell me, agree exactly
with the views of a farmer so famous for his skill as yourself!
Can it be that questioning is a kind of teaching, Ischomachus?
The fact is, I have just discovered
the plan of your series of questions!
You lead me by paths of knowledge familiar to me,
point out things like what I know,
and bring me to think that I really know things
that I thought I had no knowledge of.209

This indicates that the understanding of Socrates' dialectical method and theory of recognition was not limited to the works of Plato.

Part of the process of dialectic is for the participants to correct each other as best they can. The better they are at doing this, the more accurate is the discussion likely to be. In the discussion of knowledge Theaetetus was willing to offer his ideas because of his confidence that Socrates would point out any mistakes he made and set him right. Socrates agreed to do this as well as he could.210

Also in discussion Socrates paid close attention to the whole manner of the person, not just his words.In the Republic he treated Glaucon and Adeimantus much differently than Thrasymachus even though the debate over justice and injustice was similar. He said, "I infer this from your general character, since from your words I should have distrusted you."211 Although they were taking the same side of the argument as the angry sophist, their purpose and intention in doing so was completely different.

Another principle of the dialectical process is that each person must agree on the points as they proceed. Otherwise they would have to take a vote or a tally at the end, and the conclusion would obviously be in doubt. Even Thrasymachus agreed to this method. Socrates suggested to him, "If, as in the preceding discussion, we come to terms with one another as to what we admit in the inquiry, we shall be ourselves both judges and pleaders."212 Step-by-step agreement is what enables true progress to be made and acceptance of the eventual conclusion.

A very elevated dialectic took place in the Phaedo as Socrates endeavored to demonstrate the immortality of the soul. The setting was the prison on the last day of Socrates' life, and the topic of concern to everyone was death, which Socrates was glad to discuss. Socrates urged the others to ask any questions on this subject they might have because of their doubts and fears. He moved one step at a time, first showing that life and death are opposites which are generated out of each other like sleeping and waking, and then calling upon the doctrine of recollection to indicate that souls existed before birth which is implied by the soul's ability to understand ideals. Socrates distinguished the invisible and lasting things from the visible and corruptible things. After Cebes and Simmias agreed to reincarnation but still doubted the soul's immortality because of certain theories they had heard, Socrates dealt with their questions, very specifically refuting them by showing their contradictions with what they had already accepted about the soul. To demonstrate conceptually the immortality of the soul, Socrates needed first to gain their agreement that ideas have an absolute existence. He then went back to the generation of opposites, indicated the difference between concrete opposites and the essential opposites of the absolute ideals, and by identifying the soul with the essence of life, showed that it could not die and therefore must be immortal.213 In this example Socrates was able to use propositions which were earlier admitted as a foundation to demonstrate higher and more complicated ideas. This shows the power and comprehensiveness that the dialectical process can have.

Another common pedagogical technique that Socrates used was to summarize the main points already discussed. Often the dialectic took a roundabout course to refute or prove an argument, and it was often helpful to review the agreed-upon conclusions so that everyone would be clear on what the results were so far. In the Phaedo Socrates restated the argument of Cebes in order to be certain that he had understood it correctly.214 This is a useful technique in any communication.

In the Gorgias when Callicles became frustrated and tired of the argument, Socrates with the encouragement of Gorgias carried on the discussion by summarizing the points made and requesting corrections from Callicles.215 This allowed Socrates to bring the main points home, and eventually he lulled Callicles back into the discussion.

In Xenophon's Oikonomikos after Socrates had gotten Critobulus to recognize the value of studying estate management, he deemed it useful to recapitulate the points already discussed so that Critobulus could review them now that he was more open. In fact Critobulus found pleasure in discussing things they both agreed upon.216 Thus by means of the review the young man was able to grasp the ideas much better as he really wished to do so now that he was motivated.

The beginning of the Timaeus is devoted to a brief outline of the previous day's discussion, which is found in the Republic.213 Apparently Socrates also found it useful to review discussions from previous occasions.

The conclusions were especially joyful when there were some positive propositions which had been agreed upon, as at the close of the Philebus. A list of priorities had been drawn up showing that the suitable mean, symmetrical beauty and perfection, intelligence and wisdom, and the arts and sciences all rank above the pleasures, even the pure ones. These results were happily offered before the witness of Zeus even though all the animals of the world might assert otherwise.218 Here Socrates and his friends found particular strength in their agreement based on the inquiry even though they might be outnumbered by those who were thoughtless. The conclusion in this case became almost a firm resolve.

We have examined in considerable detail the various pedagogical techniques and methods that Socrates used by looking at many instances where he has been described employing them. The summary of these will appear in Chapter 14 where they will be compared to the methods of Confucius. To continue our descriptive portrait of Socrates as an educator we turn now to an investigation of the subjects he discussed.

Notes
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 114 发表于: 2009-03-15
SOCRATES
Content and Topics
by Sanderson Beck
Traditional Topics
Politics
Virtue
Desires, Self-control
Courage
Knowledge, Wisdom
Justice
Holiness
Friendship, Love
The Philosopher
The Good
Immortality, Soul

This chapter has been published in the book CONFUCIUS AND SOCRATES Teaching Wisdom. For ordering information, please click here.

Socrates was not only an innovator in the method which he developed, but also in the topics of conversation which he emphasized. Aristotle summarizes the original contributions of various philosophers before him, including those of Socrates and his own teacher, Plato. In his Metaphysics he indicates that when Plato was young he "first became familiar with Cratylus and with the Heraclitean doctrines that all sensible things are ever in a state of flux; these views he held even in later years."1 In the dialogue named Cratylus Plato has Socrates express the idea that all things move, flow, and change.2 The inspiration which Socrates felt during this dialogue (mentioned in the previous chapter, note 10) of which he was unsure, is probably of the Heraclitean philosophy. Socrates declares that the ideas he is expressing here are not his own.3 However, it was not unusual for Socrates to discuss whatever ideas were current and of interest to his listeners. In the Theaetetus there is a discussion of Heraclitus' notion that everything is in motion as compared to Parmenides' view that everything is at rest. If things were always changing in every way, then we would not be able to use names with any accuracy.4 Some sort of a balance of these two theories apparently seemed necessary to Socrates and Plato, as the Cratylus is itself a discussion of the origin of names, and Socrates mentions Anaxagoras' idea that notions like justice are mental.5

After mentioning Cratylus, Aristotle gives his understanding of what Socrates and Plato taught.

Socrates, however, was occupying himself with ethical matters and neglecting the world of nature as a whole, but seeking the universal in these ethical matters, and concentrated thought for the first time on definitions; Plato accepted his teaching, but held that the problem applied not to sensible things but to entities of another kind - for this reason, that the common definition could not be a definition of any sensible thing, as they were always changing. Things of this sort, then, he called Ideas, and sensible things, he said, were all named after these, and in virtue of a relation to these; for the many existed by participation in the Ideas that have the same name as they. Only the name "participation" was new; for the Pythagoreans say that things exist by "imitation" of numbers, and Plato says they exist by participation, changing the name.6

Toward the end of the same work, Aristotle repeats the same view that the idea theory was developed in response to the Heraclitean philosophy of change; ideas were differentiated from sensible things. He repeats that Socrates was concerned with the virtues of character and was the first to search for universal definitions, although Democritus had defined the hot and the cold, and the Pythagoreans had studied such things as opportunity, justice, and marriage in terms of numbers (numerology). Aristotle also credits Socrates with using inductive arguments (based on cases or examples). "But Socrates did not make the universals or the definitions exist apart: they, however, gave them separate existence, and this was the kind of thing they called Ideas."7 Certainly Socrates used definitions and was aware of universal concepts, but there is a fine line between this and Plato's Ideas as formalized entities. It is possible that Socrates could understand the difference between the visible world and the intellectual world and hold that mind is the cause of all things, as he had learned from Anaxagoras, just as he also believed that to truly know what is good is to do it, without separating ideas and knowledge from the lives and actions of people. Socrates seems to have been less theoretical and speculative than Plato and Aristotle, as he focused his energy on the practical questions of how to live the good life.

Xenophon emphasizes this point rather strongly. He states that Socrates was not concerned with "the nature of the universe" or "the laws that govern the phenomena of the heavens." He would ask those who studied these things if "their knowledge of human affairs was so complete that they must seek these new fields for the exercise of their brains; or whether it was their duty to neglect human affairs and consider only spiritual things?" Furthermore, he noticed that they never seemed to agree. "Some hold that Being is one, others that it is infinite in number; some that all things are in perpetual motion, others that nothing can ever be moved at any time; some that all life is birth and decay, others that nothing can ever be born or ever die." He also pointed out that those who study human nature can apply their knowledge for their own good and for anyone else they choose, and asked of what use was the knowledge of natural phenomena.8 It is important to note here that he was not against scientific research which might have some use, but was merely skeptical of the value of idle speculation.

Then Xenophon lists very specifically the type of questions which Socrates did discuss.

His own conversation was always considering human things, such as: What is holy, what is unholy; what is beautiful, what is shameful; what is just, what is unjust; what is prudence, what is madness; what is courage, what is cowardice; what is a state, what is a statesman; what is government, what is a governor; other such questions the knowledge of which made "gentlemen" (good and noble men), while ignorance should involve the reproach of "slavishness."9

Before we examine Socrates' views on each of these topics, let us first consider his attitude toward the more customary educational pursuits of his time.

Traditional Topics
The usual education for the young Greek citizen consisted of gymnastics, music, and grammar. Gymnastics refers to the various aspects of physical training including preparation for fighting in battle. Music to the Greeks meant the various arts of the Muses such as playing the harp and flute, singing, dancing, poetry, and perhaps painting and sculpture. Grammar involved learning to read and write. Socrates supported the idea of studying these basic subjects, although he was not a teacher of them.

Socrates exercised his own body and recommended that others do so also. Xenophon records how he counseled Epigenes, who was out of shape, on the value of physical training. Epigenes rationalizes that he is not an athlete, but Socrates points out that in case of war it is those in bad condition who are killed or disgrace themselves, while the physically fit fight valiantly and can help their friends. Even though military training is not required by the state, he ought to consider the advantages of good health due to physical conditioning. Bad conditioning and bad health can even lead to loss of memory, depression, discontent, and insanity.10 In another passage Xenophon tells us that Socrates very seriously urged his companions to take care of their health. His advice centered around the idea that each person should understand his own unique characteristics.

You should learn all you can from those who know. Everyone should watch himself throughout his life, and notice what sort of meat and drink and what form of exercise suit his constitution, and he should regulate them in order to enjoy good health. For by such attention to yourselves you can discover better than any doctor what suits your constitution.11

In Xenophon's Symposium Socrates praises the dancing of a boy at the banquet, because he used all parts of his body actively. Then he requested to learn the steps from the dancing master. The others laughed when he said he wanted to dance, but Socrates asks in a series of rhetorical questions whether they were laughing because he wished to improve his health, or get more pleasure from food and sleep, or so that unlike long-distance runners and boxers he can give his body a symmetrical development by exercising his arms and legs, or because he will not need a partner for exercise, or because he can do it in any convenient place, or are they laughing because he has a large paunch and wants to reduce it. In fact Charmides had caught him dancing just the other day, and after he had heard the reasons he went home and practiced shadow-boxing.12

In Plato's Republic we have Socrates' polished view of gymnastics and its relation to music. He suggests that training begin in early years and continue through life. Socrates reminds his listeners that it is the soul which improves the body, and not the reverse. Discipline of bodily habits is especially important for the guardians of the state. This would prohibit excessive sleep, fancy dinners, courtesans, and other luxuries. They should have no need of lawyers and doctors who invent names for diseases and prolong illnesses by pampering them. In Plato's view the healthy should live and the diseased should be left to die.12 Whether Socrates' attitude was this harsh is hard to say.

The traditional view was that gymnastics was for the body and music for the soul. However, Socrates here indicates that the purpose of exercise was not just to build muscles, but to stimulate the courageous spirit. Socrates describes the danger of too much gymnastics without music as a harsh and ferocious temper, while the opposite extreme leads to softness and effeminacy. By balancing the two together the philosopher will be gentle yet strong.

When a man allows music to play upon him and to pour into his soul through the funnel of his ears those sweet and soft and melancholy airs, his whole life being spent in the delights of song: in the first stage of the process the spirit within him is tempered like iron and made useful, instead of brittle and useless. But if he carries on the softening and soothing process, in the next stage he begins to melt and dissipate, until he has wasted away his spirit and cut out the muscles of his soul; he becomes a feeble warrior.

If the spirit is naturally weak in him he reaches this result quickly, but if he is high-spirited the weakening makes him excitable, easily irritated by the slightest provocation, and as quickly burnt out. Instead of being spirited he becomes irritable, peevish, and discontented.

In gymnastics, if a man takes hard exercise and is a great eater, not engaging in music and philosophy, at first the fitness of his body fills him with pride and spirit; he becomes braver and bolder than he was. Then what happens? If he does nothing else and has no contact with the Muses, does not even that love of learning in his soul, having no taste of study or inquiry or discussion or the arts, become feeble, deaf, and blind, since his mind never wakes up or receives nourishment, nor are his senses purified? He ends up becoming a hater of reasoning, unmusical, and never using persuasion by words, he achieves all his ends like a beast by violence and savagery; in his ignorance and ineptitude he lives without propriety and grace.

As there are these two principles of human nature, I would say some god gave to mankind these two arts, music and gymnastics, for the service of the spirited and philosophical in them (only indirectly for the soul and body), in order that they may be harmoniously adjusted by the proper degree of tension and relaxation in each. Then he who blends gymnastics with music and applies them most appropriately to the soul is the one we may most correctly call the perfect musician and harmonist, much more than the tuner of strings.13

In the Republic Socrates and his friends agree that music and poetry are useful in the important early education, although they felt there should be censorship for the protection of the children. The false and ignominious stories about the gods which the poets have invented should be eliminated, for the young are not able to understand the allegorical meanings. God is good and should be portrayed as such. God would not represent himself falsely; the lies of the poets are not useful to the gods or to men; therefore the false tales are to be rejected.14 Discouraging and erroneous myths about the underworld and the nature of the soul also must be cast out in order to remove the fear of death. Weakening and pitiful lamentations should be avoided as should excessive laughter at the expense of the gods. The poets should not show the heroes behaving oppositely to the virtues and qualities of good character. The purpose of poetry is to reveal the truth, not what is false.15 Socrates would have poetry show people admirable examples so that there would be positive patterns for the masses to follow.

In terms of style, Socrates, saw tragedy and comedy as imitative, some poetry as simply narrative, and epic poetry as a combination of the two. The guardians should not imitate bad qualities. The musical harmonies and rhythms can be simple or complex, but the simple ones are to be preferred since the others may be confusing. The harmonies which are soft and indolent are not considered to be beneficial to the education for strong character; rather the military strains which lead to self-control and courage are to be selected. Musical instruments are to be reduced to the lyre and harp for the city and the pipe for the country shepherds. Harmony is an important quality, but it is chiefly to be found in the life of virtue where the beauty of the soul harmonizes with the beauty of the body. Love should be true, temperate, and free of sensual indulgence and crudeness.16

Such a radical proposal does not appear in the works of Xenophon or any other Socratic except Plato, and it is therefore likely that he has taken some ideas of his teacher and gone beyond them. Although we may not agree on all the reasoning or the conclusions because many important values may not have been examined (such as Aristotle's purgation of the emotions theory), still it is useful to note the search for the ideal development of character always keeping the good in mind. In this sense the discussion is Socratic, as Socrates was always investigating what is beneficial for man.

In Book X Plato again represents poetry as inferior, because it is imitative. Here is perhaps Plato's most definitive statements of the ideas as separate entities (except perhaps the Seventh Letter) which Aristotle has told us was Plato's unique contribution. Here three levels are presented. There is the single idea of the bed as created by God, physical beds made by carpenters, and representation of a bed as imitated by a poet or painter. This last is only an imitation of the appearance of the physical bed which is based on the idea of a bed. Therefore the poetic and artistic imitator is the farthest from truth and real knowledge. There are three arts related here. The user of a things knows it best from actual experience. The maker is instructed by the user and has belief but not knowledge. The imitator has neither belief nor knowledge.

Poetry is also seen here as being deceptive and as dragging people down into negative emotions such as pity, sorrow, fear, buffoonery, etc. Although they admit that they love poetry, according to these arguments they must expel it from the ideal state.17 It is also useful to keep in mind that the purpose of this discussion is to delineate the perfectly just state, and that poetry is being examined here in relation to that according to certain definite criteria. This author feels that these criticisms of poetry are certainly open to criticism themselves, but this is not the place to explore those areas.

Even disregarding the radical ideas of Plato, Socrates could certainly be critical of poets and rhapsodes. In Xenophon's Symposium he agrees with Antisthenes' comment that these reciters who have memorized Homer are not really wise. "No," said Socrates, "and the reason is clear: they do not know the inner meaning of the poems."18 Here we can perhaps infer that Socrates places some value on understanding the inner meaning of poetry.

In Plato's Apology Socrates tells how he discovered that the poets are not wise but rather inspired as are prophets and oracles.19 At the end of Plato's Symposium we find Socrates arguing with the drowsy Agathon and Aristophanes that the genius (spirit which does the inspiring) of tragedy and comedy are the same.20 Because of his own genius, or divine sign, it is possible that Socrates placed more value on inspiration than the rationalistic Plato, even though Socrates recognized that inspiration did not necessarily give true wisdom.

The Ion shows Socrates questioning a Homeric rhapsode to see if he possessed the wisdom concerning what is portrayed in the poems. Socrates discovers that this reciter is not able to answer questions about the material to demonstrate that he is wise. Using the analogy of the magnet Socrates concludes that God inspires the poet who inspires the rhapsode who inspires the listeners.21 Since he was primarily searching for wisdom, Socrates discovered that poetry was not the answer.

In discussing the ideal state in the Republic Socrates argues that women should receive the same education as men since their nature is not essentially different for learning. Here again we have a very theoretical discussion, considering that there were no women disciples of Socrates. Another radical idea which was not practiced as far as we know was the plan that the guardians should have their wives and children in common. This revolutionary challenge to the family system has not been adopted by any major culture. The reasoning here is to substitute a wider expansion of love and brotherhood among the whole community rather than limiting it to the family. However, results so far have shown that blood is still thicker than water. Matrimony was still to be held sacred while licentiousness was discouraged, but the plan to do so was to reward heroism and excellence with conjugal freedoms - a kind of aristocratic eugenics. The others were to be deceived by telling them the pairings were due to a lottery. Women were to bear children from the age of twenty to forty, while men could beget from twenty-five to fifty-five. Children were not to know who their physical parents were, but the entire state was to be as one family. Children would have special nurses and be trained for war.22

It is hard to imagine the practical side of Socrates suggesting such a contrived and artificial system except merely as an interesting topic of discussion. In fact the ideal state for Socrates did not require an army, because all the citizens would live moderate and self-controlled lives. It is only when Glaucon, Plato's brother, objects to the simplicity of this life-style and requests that they have the modern conveniences of sofas, dining tables, sauces, sweets, etc. that Socrates realizes that they wish to examine not the best state but a luxurious state. He agrees to this as an exercise to see what the origins of justice and injustice are.23 Therefore the breakdown of the family and private lives of the citizens in this greedy and feverish state is more a result of the dialectical proposal of his listeners than it is his own personal recommendation. The result from this point of view represents more of a compromise with the reality of people's greed and lusts than a portrayal of the true and practical ideal of Socrates' personal life-style.

Socrates occasionally discussed women, children, family, and education. He often recommended the famous lady, Aspasia, as a teacher. As the mistress of Pericles, she was believed by some to be the "power behind the throne." A few fragments and references to the dialogue of Aeschines called Aspasia indicate that Socrates recommended her to Callias for the education of his children. He is surprised that men could be educated by a woman, but Socrates describes the achievements of some of the famous women in history. Aspasia not only influenced Pericles, but raised Lysicles after Pericles' death from obscurity to a prominent position in Athens. He then describes a counseling session she did for Xenophon and his wife. She Socratically asks them if they prefer the more valuable possessions of their neighbors to their own lesser ones, and they do. Then she asks if they would prefer to have their neighbor's husband or wife if they were better, and they are each silent. Her conclusion is that they ought to improve themselves so that they each will have the best husband and the most excellent wife.24 Socrates apparently had great respect for women who were truly wise.

In Xenophon's Oeconomicus there is a long description of how Ischomachus educated his wife to cooperate with him in household management. Socrates appears to be very eager to learn these things and pass them on to the inquiring Critobulus.25 Diogenes Laertius records a clever quip of Socrates when someone asked him whether he should marry or not. He replied, "Whichever you do you will regret it."26 This comment really struck a chord in the indecisive Kierkegaard.

Xenophon narrates an extended lesson given by Socrates to his son Lamprocles when he observed the young man's attitude toward his mother was negative. He reminded him of the gratitude he ought to have towards her for all the benefits she had given him. He explains how a man chooses a wife to bear his own children, how she labors for the child, giving her own food, and after birth raises and cares for it, how she guesses the needs and likes of the child and supplies all these things over many years without knowing what she will get in return. He asks if Xanthippe's brutality is worse than a wild beast's or her words any more harmful than an actor's threats in a tragedy. Does not she do everything she can for his own good? Parents are more deserving than anyone of gratitude, and if he is ungrateful to them, what will other people or the gods think of him?27 According to Xenophon, Socrates' feelings of family loyalty were very strong.

This is further demonstrated in his counseling of Chaerecrates, the brother of Chaerophon, when Socrates discovered they had been quarreling with each other. He points out to Chaerecrates that he only has one brother, even if they do have to share the family's possessions. Is not community better than solitude? Why cannot there be friendship between brothers? "Common parentage and common upbringing are strong ties of affection."28 However, Chaerecrates says that Chaerophon treats him worse than everyone else. Socrates asks if he can manage a horse without knowing the right way. Although Chaerecrates is willing to return kindness for kindness, his brother only annoys him. Socrates suggests that he can tame a growling dog by kindness rather than by getting angry. Chaerecrates feels the need for some wisdom, and Socrates asks him if he wanted an invitation to dinner, what would he do? He replies that he would first extend an invitation. A similar process would work in doing a favor for the other person. Socrates suggests that Chaerecrates, even though he is the younger, is the most worthy to begin this process of kindness. "Worthless people, it is true, yield most readily to gifts, but kindness is used to be most successful with a gentleman."29 Socrates offers the analogy of the hands which are given by God to help each other? Hands cannot stretch more than six feet apart, but brothers can help each other at long range.30 Again Xenophon shows us the practical Socrates, offering good advice in personal situations as they arise.

Xenophon gives us a pragmatic Socrates also in terms of the extent the study of any given subject should go, the criterion being usefulness. In geometry that meant being able to measure and divide land and compute the yield. Xenophon writes that Socrates was not unfamiliar with the more complicated problems; but he felt that they could take up a lifetime, and there were more useful studies.31

Astronomy was similarly held to be valuable as far as it was useful, which was to tell the time of day, month or year, and for navigation. Socrates attended lectures on the revolutions of the planets and such things, but Xenophon deprecates the investigations of Anaxagoras regarding the heavenly machinery and that the sun is fire and points out some of the differences - notably that sunlight is essential to vegetation while fire withers things. Arithmetic likewise was to be studied as far as it was useful.32 Here Xenophon seems to be giving his own experience with Socrates and also defending him against the charges which were leveled at Anaxagoras and other innovative thinkers. He does hint that Socrates had curiosity and knowledge in these areas. It is likely that Socrates was probably somewhere in between Xenophon and Plato on these points, or perhaps he comprehended them both. Plato's views will be discussed when we examine the education of the philosopher.

In his treatise, the Oeconomicus, Xenophon gives us a Socratic definition on estate management. Socrates begins by showing the young Critobulus that it is valuable to be able to manage one's property and possessions well, and that true wealth is what is useful and beneficial. Therefore the correct use of money and possessions is very important. Next he aids Critobulus in becoming aware that he needs to learn how to manage his money better. Then Socrates delineates the elements of household management. For studying the relationship between the husband and the wife, he offers to introduce the young man to Aspasia. Socrates discourses for a while on the values which farming teaches. When Critobulus asks what makes some farmers so much more successful than others, Socrates recounts a long interview he had with the gentleman Ischomachus. Socrates draws the successful gentleman out on how he educated his wife to cooperate with him in managing the household in a well-ordered and industrious manner, and how he taught his wife to change from using cosmetics to the natural beauty of good character. Socrates who only considers himself to be an idle chatterer and not a true gentleman, asks Ischomachus to explain the occupations of a gentleman. Then Ischomachus describes his piety toward the gods and his pursuit of wealth so that he can benefit his friends and the city. He describes his daily routine as a country gentleman in taking care of his farm and servants. He explains to Socrates how he educates his stewards to good will, diligence, as supervisors, and to be just. Ischomachus teaches Socrates the art of agriculture by Socratic discussion from the nature of the land and soil to sowing, reaping, threshing, and winnowing to planting; he gives a summation of the art of farming as taking loving care of everything, and gives a description of the kingly man.33

This dialogue has often been ignored by Socratic scholars as merely the views of Xenophon, but a careful examination shows not only the use of Socratic questioning, but also his helpfulness in counseling Critobulus, his defining of the subject, his step-by-step reasoning, and even the pedagogy used by Ischomachus on his wife and servants, and the ideals towards which he educated them. Naturally Xenophon was more interested in estate management and agriculture than Socrates was, but continuously Socrates demonstrates the desire and ability to discourse intelligently with people on any subject of concern to them. Apparently Xenophon's personal philosophy was much influenced by his contact with Socrates when he was a young man. Again Xenophon portrays for us a pragmatic Socrates who by his conversation becomes extraordinarily useful to his friends.

Xenophon also described some of Socrates' visits to the artisans for which he was well-known. In conversing with an armorer whose breastplates were more expensive than others, Socrates discovers that they are better due to his making them with better proportions so that they fit and are easier to wear. Socrates points out that some people's bodies are not well-proportioned. How then can he make it well-proportioned? The answer is that he makes it to fit, and a good fit is well-proportioned in this case.34 Here the ideal is not a pre-conceived pattern of beauty, but rather what is going to be practical for the individual.

Xenophon gives a Socrates with a different point of view on art than is found in Plato. When he visited the house of a painter, he asked him if painting is a representation of things seen. It is. Then he asks if artists in copying types of beauty have difficulty finding a perfect model, and therefore combine the beautiful details of several to make the whole figure look beautiful. They do. He inquires whether they can reproduce the character of the soul. The painter asks in response how they could imitate what is not visible. Now Socrates begins to probe for the subtle and real level of experience.

"Do people commonly express the feelings of sympathy and aversion by their looks?"

"I think so."

"Then cannot this much be imitated in the eyes?"

"Undoubtedly."

"Does it seem to you that the joys and sorrows of their friends produce the same expression on men's faces, whether they really care or not?"

"Oh no, of course not; they look radiant at their joys, and downcast at their sorrows."

"Then is it possible to represent these looks too?"

"Undoubtedly."

"Moreover, nobility and dignity, self-abasement and servility, prudence and understanding, insolence and vulgarity, are reflected in the face and in the attitudes of the body whether still or in motion."

"What you say is true."

"Then these, too, can be imitated, can't they?"

"Undoubtedly."

"Now which do you think the more pleasant sight, people who reflect a beautiful and good and lovable character, or those who are shameful and worthless and hateful?"

"By God, there is a great difference, Socrates."35

Socrates has a similar conversation with a sculptor about "faithfully representing the form of living beings" by careful and accurate attention to details such as "the flesh wrinkled or tense, the limbs compressed or outstretched, the muscles taut or loose." These make it more convincing. Socrates further points out, "Does not the exact imitation of the feelings that affect bodies in action also produce a sense of satisfaction in the spectator?" If these feelings are accurately portrayed, "It follows, then, that the sculptor must represent in his figures the activities of the soul."36

It is clear that Socrates understood art as an imitation, but in these cases he does not make a judgment about it being farthest removed from reality. Rather he focuses the attention of the artists on the soul and the human expression, perhaps so that they could improve the quality of their work to the benefit of them and the spectators.

Since just about all he ever did was talk with people, the study of language was important for Socrates. Prodicus was the reigning expert on grammar and semantics, but Socrates admits that he was too poor to take his fifty-drachma course.37 However, in the Cratylus Plato shows Socrates in long discussion on the meaning of names and the origins of words. A unique characteristic of language is that it can be true or false. Things and actions have their own reality and nature. Is this true of speaking? Teachers use names and words as instruments, and therefore must depend on the lawgiver, or inventor of names. The sound and the form of the syllables ought to fit the thing named. Since the user of something knows it best, the dialectician, who uses words in question and answer, ought to guide the lawgivers or name-makers. Then Socrates analyzes many names from Homer to show how the name matches the nature of the man. Assuming that the first inventors of names must have been philosophers, Socrates indicates the hidden meaning or origin of various concepts and names of gods. These are often somewhat contrived or fanciful explanations in order to make certain points. Most names are derived from other words, and some have foreign origins. However, the earliest roots of words were invented according to the sounds of the letters and the rhythm of speaking. Socrates then analyzes the basic meanings of the different letters.38

Socrates asks Cratylus if he agrees with the discussion he has just had with Hermogenes, but Cratylus denies that names can be false at all. For Socrates language is an imitation like pictures and therefore may be an imperfect or false portrayal of the reality. Socrates points out that although the ideal is for the sounds to reflect the meaning, many words are merely based on customary usage. The result is that the meanings of many words are contradictory to their expression. Cratylus has held that knowledge of words gives knowledge of the reality, but Socrates asks about the very first name-makers and the distinctions we can make between the true and false use of language. Therefore we must be able to know things without words. Is it not better to know the things themselves rather than their names? However, if everything is always changing, then we could never really know anything. "But if that which knows and that which is known exist forever, and the beautiful and the good and every other thing also exist, then I do not think that they can resemble a process of flux, as we were just now supposing." Therefore Socrates cautions Cratylus concerning the doctrines of Heraclitus and warns him not to be led astray from reality simply by the power of names.39 Socrates loved to play with words and their meanings as his tools in the dialectic, but he was also aware of their danger in being able to be true or false, and of their limitations as being only a representation of reality.

Rhetoric was a subject introduced by the sophists which became quite popular in the time of Socrates. Those who wished to be successful in the political assembly or the law courts would pay money to learn how to be a good speaker. The best of the rhetoric teachers was said to be Gorgias, and Plato portrayed him in a discussion with Socrates. Socrates asks him what rhetoric is, and discovers that it is the art of persuasion using words. However, when Gorgias adds that it is used in the courts and assemblies concerning the just and unjust, Socrates labors to show him that since it can be used for right or wrong it cannot of itself be just. Socrates in fact defines rhetoric as a kind of flattery rather than a true art, which is always concerned with what is good.40 Its relationship to other arts and flatteries has been discussed in the previous chapter. (Note 163)

Another well-known rhetorician was Lysias, and in the Phaedrus Socrates gives a critique of what is said to be a speech written by Lysias. To do this Socrates ignores the content and examines the rhetorical manner which he found repetitive.41 After giving a couple of speeches himself, Socrates discusses with Phaedrus the principles of good and bad speaking. First the speaker should know the truth, but this is not enough to persuade, just as the art of speaking cannot be divorced from the truth. Even the deceiver has to know the truth and how to disguise things in its likeness. In further criticizing Lysias' speech Socrates indicates the features it lacked. The speech ought to be organized like a body with head and feet. The subject should be defined to show its unity and then classified into its various divisions. A speech should begin with an introduction, followed by a presentation of facts, third comes the proofs, fourth the future probabilities, then confirmation and refutation, and finally the summation. Ultimately oratory is the art of enchanting the soul, and the orator therefore should learn the differences of human nature by experience and reflection so that his speech can be perfectly suited to his listeners. But the highest form of rhetoric is to speak what is acceptable to God.42 Here Socrates has described the various levels of rhetoric from the art of clever lying to the textbook outline of the speech to the human psychology of communication and ultimately to the ethical and mystical oneness with God.

The dialogue concludes with Socrates' critique of the written word as being artificial rather than alive in that one cannot ask it questions. Books serve though for recreation and amusement and as memorials to be treasured against the forgetfulness of age. However, dialectic is a far more serious and useful art.43

Politics
Another traditional subject related to politics was the science of warfare. Xenophon records how one of Socrates' companions desired to become a general. Socrates points out to him that if the state is to trust him he had better learn the art of the general. The man returned after studying tactics, whereupon Socrates indicates various other aspects of generalship such as providing equipment and supplies, and he must be "resourceful, active, careful, hardy, and quick-witted." If he is to arrange the men properly, he must be able to tell the good men from the bad. Finally Socrates sends the man back to his tutor for more instruction.44 Understanding the personal goal of the man, Socrates was able to guide him and test him so that he could move closer to it.

On another occasion Socrates questioned a man who had been chosen as a cavalry commander. Since he has never been selected as the commander of the horses and their riders, he ought to know how to improve the horses. This being understood, Socrates suggests that he look to improving the men by training them to mount and fight in the kind of terrain occupied by the enemy. He must also raise their spirits and give them courage by his speaking ability.45 The result was that the man became more aware of his duties as a cavalry officer.

Nicomachides, a scarred veteran of battle, complained once to Socrates that the Athenians had elected a business-man as general. Socrates points out to him that the man has demonstrated his skill at handling men and supplies in that his choruses have always won the prize in the theater. A good businessman knows how to: make subordinates willing and obedient, put the right man in the right place, punish the bad and reward the good, win the goodwill of those under him, gain allies, keep what he has, and be strenuous and industrious in his work; all of these abilities are required by a good general. The only difference is the fighting, and yet the businessman knows the economic advantages of victory and the heavy losses of defeat. Success in public affairs is very similar to success in private life.46 Thus Socrates helped the man gain a wider perspective of the situation and perhaps to become more accepting of the choice.

Xenophon also recorded a conversation between Socrates and Pericles' son prior to a war with Boeotia in which he gives the young Pericles numerous suggestions for raising the Athenians' morale and even some strategic ideas for defending Athens. In drawing upon the past experience of the Athenians, Socrates continually looks at how it could be of positive advantage to them. Their heroic pride should be a heritage of inspiration, and their recent defeats should sober them up to take these challenges seriously. Even though their military discipline and training is slack compared to the Spartans, yet they do maintain their ships, excel in athletics, and obediently follow the chorus-trainers.47 Socrates knew when and how to meet discouragement with intelligent reasoning and even a pep talk to encourage a positive attitude.

Whereas Xenophon shows Socrates giving practical suggestions in real, historical situations, Plato describes some of Socrates' ideal plans in the Republic. Children were to be trained and prepared for war by having the opportunity to observe battles from a safe distance. Cowards were to be demoted and heroes rewarded with honor and favors from their beloveds. No Greeks were to be enslaved, and the soldiers were to exercise self-control by not despoiling the enemy's dead. In fact fighting between Greeks is especially discordant and should be replaced by friendship among all Greeks.48 The purpose here, which may be more Platonic than Socratic, is to provide incentives for courageous deeds.

Most of the Republic is an attempt to formulate a just state, and even though they recognize it does not exist anywhere on earth, Socrates indicates there is a divine pattern in heaven for whoever wishes to contemplate it.49 The state they are imagining begins with a simple life based on a division of labor. Once luxuries are requested, expansion of territory and war become necessary.50 Specialization leads to a division of classes also. The guardians, however, will have no money or private property; therefore the soldiers will be disciplined and self- controlled. The state must remain small enough to remain unified and well-ordered. The statesmen should exemplify wisdom, the guardians courage, and the whole state must be temperate and self-controlled. Justice will result when each person does his own proper business.51 This form of government is called aristocracy, originally meaning rule by the virtuous or most excellent. Although this type of government had never been found, Socrates had made a careful study of political systems and apparently was the first not only to propose an ideal but also to delineate the major patterns of government he had observed.
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 115 发表于: 2009-03-15
In Book VIII he describes the four principal political systems and how each tends to degenerate from the one immediately above. He shows also how the larger state reflects the individual psychology which is prevalent in the community. "States," he said, "are as men are, because they grow out of human characters."52 Timocracy which is government based on honor and ambition, develops out of aristocracy due to negligent eugenics and the rise of the military character over the philosophical nature. The timocratic man loses interest in culture and becomes ambitious. He treats slaves with contempt but is respectful to free men, is obedient to authority and a lover of honor and power. He despises riches when young but becomes avaricious when older, forgetting virtue. This character is formed when his mother is always complaining that her husband and her have lost their prestige because he is not eager to struggle for power or money as he lets his thoughts center within himself. The servants also encourage the boy to strive for honor and position while his father attempts to give him wisdom. The result is: "He being not originally of a bad nature, but having kept bad company, is finally brought by their mutual influence to a middle point, and gives up the kingdom which is within him to the middle principle of aggression and passion, and becomes arrogant and ambitious."53

Oligarchy or plutocracy, which is the rule of the wealthy, occurs due to an increase in the private accumulation and expenditure of money. As the citizens grow richer, they think less of virtue, and soon rich men are honored above all others. They become lovers of money, and possession of property becomes a qualification for citizenship. Now neither the wise nor the honorable are ruling, but merely the rich. Another result is that as the rich get richer and the poor are excluded, there develops two states in conflict with each other. The rulers are few and have no courage for battle; but if they arm the masses, they become more afraid of them than the enemy. Also their love of money makes them unwilling to pay taxes. Those who are driven out of business or lose their jobs become the unemployed and useless drones who drain the state and often turn criminal. How does the plutocratic man arise? When he sees his father pursuing honor and ambition but floundering on the sinking ship of state as his position of prestige and his property are taken from him, the son humbled by poverty looks down on ambition and strives only to become wealthy. To do so he becomes frugal and stingy, even cheating if the opportunity presents itself.54

Democracy develops as the powerful wealthy buy up the estates of the spendthrift youth. The poor are becoming eager for revolution, but the rich mollify the drones by giving them hand-outs. The rich meanwhile live in luxury and idleness, caring only for pleasure as they ignore virtue and the poor. Finally on some pilgrimage or march the lean poor men notice the weakness of the fat rich. Realizing their natural strength and the weakness of the divided state, the poor classes either by revolution or some other means take over the government. Then everyone has an equal share of freedom and power, and governmental officials are elected. Due to the freedom this spangled state will have a variety of characters and constitutions. There is a great tolerance even in forgiving condemned criminals, but in this wild liberty many principles of order and good taste are trampled under foot by the mob. The democratic man originates as his miserly father tries to train him in his middle-class ways, but the son becomes enamored of pleasures and desires which are tacitly valued. He associates with the drones and eventually his desires and pleasures overcome his miserly upbringing, often after a fierce battle within himself. He calls insolence breeding, anarchy liberty, waste generosity, and impudence courage; the young man trained in necessity becomes a libertine of useless pleasures. He cares not who is in the government as they are all the same to him, and he spends his life going from one fad to the next.55

Tyranny results from the insatiable desire for freedom in democracy. The democrats wish the rulers to be like the subjects and to give in to their every whim. The family situation is parallel as the sons no longer respect or obey their parents, since all are equal. The teachers fear and flatter their students, and the old condescend to adopt the gay and frivolous manners of the young, not wishing to be thought unpopular or authoritative. All classes and both sexes are considered equal and free. Even the dogs and other animals run around free and undisciplined. No one cares for laws or any kind of authority. As excessive love for money brought the economic downfall of the plutocracy, excessive freedom in democracy leads to the slavery of a tyranny. In democracy the idle drones increase and feed off of the wealthy class and the working class. When the well-to-do and workers begin to defend themselves against these infringements, the people find a protector who once he has tasted blood, requests a body-guard, and eventually becomes a dictator, liberating debtors and distributing land to his followers. He is always stirring up wars and taxing his people. Any resistance to his authority is considered as traitorously aiding the enemy and is ruthlessly destroyed. To maintain his rule he must rid the state of the wise, wealthy, and valiant who might challenge his supremacy. This inverted purgation removes the best and leaves the worst. Those willing to be enslaved by him become his supporters. The tyrant seizes the public treasuries and when these are exhausted, lives off the people. If they rebel, he punishes them cruelly.56

This understanding of the types of political systems and human characters was probably elaborated and embellished a great deal by Plato, but it is undoubtedly true that Socrates studied and discussed these questions with a depth and clarity never before approached. Xenophon gives us only Socrates' brief definitions of the forms of government.

Kingship and tyranny in his judgment were both forms of government, but he believed that they differed. For government of the people with their consent and in accordance with the laws of the state was kingship; while government of unwilling subjects not controlled by laws, but imposed by the will of the ruler, was tyranny. And where the officials are chosen among those who fulfill the requirements of the laws, the constitution is an aristocracy; where ratable property is the qualification for office, it is a plutocracy; where all are eligible, a democracy.57

Socrates considered it his duty to educate capable men for politics even though he did not participate in government himself. When he was criticized by Antiphon for avoiding politics, Socrates replied, "How, Antiphon, should I play a more important part in politics, by engaging in it alone, or by taking care to turn out as many competent politicians as possible?"58 Socrates often counseled his companions on how to prepare oneself to be a good ruler. Even though Aristippus turned out not to be interested in government, Socrates indicated in conversation with him the need for self-control as a training for rulership.59

Xenophon also records a conversation between Socrates and Glaucon reminiscent of those with Euthydemus and Alcibiades. Glaucon is anxious to become an orator and was striving to rise in politics even though he was still a teenager. He was being dragged from platforms and was a laughing-stock, and so Socrates took an interest in him for the sake of his brother Plato and uncle Charmides. Socrates gets his attention by appealing to his ambition, and then proceeds to question him on questions of government. Would he benefit the city by making it richer? Yes, but Glaucon has no knowledge of the city's revenues nor of its expenditures. Glaucon suggests he would get wealth from the enemies, but he has no knowledge of the relative strength of the city and its enemies, nor of its defenses, which are already weak. He does not know why the silver mines are no longer producing as much, or even how much wheat is available to feed the population. One must know the needs even of one household in order to manage it successfully, yet Glaucon cannot even help his uncle. Glaucon's excuse is that his uncle will not listen to him, but if he cannot persuade one man, how could he ever get all the Athenians to listen to him? Socrates points out the dangers of acting out of ignorance and suggests that Glaucon gain the needed knowledge if he wishes to enter public life.60 On the other hand Socrates advised Glaucon's uncle, Charmides, to use his ability and knowledge to serve the state, since he had something valuable to offer.61 In Xenophon, Socrates' lessons on politics were personal and practical for the individual.

In Plato's Republic Socrates also discusses politics with Glaucon, but here they are attempting to formulate universal principles. They give special attention to the qualities of character needed for their ideal rulers. The elders should rule, and the younger should serve. The candidates for rulership should be tested in every stage of their life to make sure that they always do what is for the good of the country regardless of the temptations of pleasure or fear. Only those who have the inner golden quality of a virtuous character are to be selected as leaders.62

Finally Socrates proposes that the ideal is for philosophers to be kings, and until the political leaders become wise the human race will have no rest from evils. The correct use of knowledge, not mere belief or opinion which can err, is the sure guide in all action. The true philosopher loves truth and wisdom and the joys of the soul above all else; consequently he will be temperate, gentle, sociable, very intelligent, and harmonious. However, the name of philosophy has been corrupted by sophistry and the failure of society to recognize and make use of the true philosophers. The true philosopher is rare, because it is easy for one's philosophical nature to deteriorate, for many reasons. There are few from the beginning. One strong virtue may overshadow the others and prevent the development of a well-rounded character. Beauty, wealth, strength, rank, and other prizes of life may distract and corrupt. The finer and more subtle natures are often more susceptible to negative influences. The public opinion of the masses and the force of the crowd may sway them. They may even be tried or put to death. The only consolation for the philosopher is that he may come to good and be saved by the power of God. When the society is not receptive to the wisdom of the real philosopher, then he can only live his own life in goodwill, keeping himself pure from injustice. Unfortunately Socrates felt that there was no state in existence at that time capable of adapting to the philosopher king.63 Nevertheless Socrates must have believed that it was worthwhile to strive toward the ideal, and they must know what it is in order to do it.

Virtue
Usually the discussions of Socrates would focus around how to become virtuous or attain excellence. Virtue was discussed in this general sense and also more specifically in terms of self-control, courage, wisdom, justice, and holiness. In the Alcibiades I Socrates convinces the young man that what people really need in order to be happy is virtue. Therefore, if he is to help the state, Alcibiades must first become virtuous himself, and this is done by looking at what is divine and bright, and acting accordingly. Only the virtuous can govern correctly; virtue makes a man free, while vice enslaves.64

In the Laches Socrates is consulted by two gentlemen to see how their sons' souls may be improved and made virtuous or excellent.65 A frequently mentioned assumption is that each human faculty has its natural function, and virtue is what enables it to function at its best. Socrates gives the example of the eyes; their proper excellence or virtue is seeing. Accomplishing anything in the world depends on the soul, and consequently happiness or success depends on the virtue or excellent functioning of the soul.66

We have described in the previous chapter Socrates' attempts in the Meno to define virtue and discover whether it can be taught. Many ideas were examined, but the results were not conclusive. The main definition they consider is that virtue is the ability to attain what is good. However, Meno is not able to defend this when Socrates introduces a case where someone attains what he thinks is good by unjust means.67 However, this refutation could be easily challenged by showing that one cannot attain true goodness by unjust means. If injustice is bad for someone, how can this be "attaining what is good?"

Meno is more concerned with whether virtue can be taught. They agree that virtue is wisdom, and since wisdom is the right use of knowledge, and knowledge can be taught; then virtue can be taught. However, they are not able to verify this by finding any teachers of virtue.68 There is some confusion here also, because often wisdom is considered only to be a part of virtue. Even if wisdom can be taught, that does not mean that all of virtue can be taught.

Since they agree that there are some virtuous people, Socrates suggests that virtue may be merely due to right belief gained by divine inspiration.69 This idea is not refuted, and it is an explanation of the phenomena.

In the Protagoras Socrates questions the master sophist on what he proposes to teach young men - virtue. Socrates asks whether justice and temperance and holiness are parts of virtue which is one whole. Protagoras agrees, saying they are like the parts of the face. Socrates reveals a contradiction in his argument in that some of these parts of virtue can have the same opposite.70 However, Socrates ends up showing that the virtues depend on knowledge and therefore are teachable.71 The assumption again is that virtue is inseparable from wisdom. This position is also maintained by Socrates in the Phaedo where he further states that the virtues without wisdom are only a shadow of virtue and have no freedom or health or truth in themselves alone.72

A fundamental belief or axiomatic truth for Socrates was the idea that no one desires what they know is evil. Or, in the positive, everyone desires what they believe is good. This is a basic psychological principle of motivation. However, this does not mean that everyone knows what is good, nor does it deny that a person may think something is bad and still do it. Actually it is a pragmatic principle which verifies people's values on the basis of their actions. In other words, everyone is doing the best they can with what they know. In the Meno Socrates clarifies, "They desire what they suppose to be goods, although they are really evils."73

Socrates expresses the same idea in the Protagoras. "For no wise man, as I believe, will admit that any person errs willingly, or willingly does evil and dishonorable actions; but they are well aware that all who do evil and dishonorable things do them against their will."74 Xenophon has Socrates saying the same belief, "that all naturally love whatever they think will benefit them."75

This premise leads to another important belief of Socrates, and that is that the remedy for bad action is to educate the person so he will know what is good. Both Xenophon and Plato indicate that Socrates recommended instruction rather than punishment for those who are in ignorance. Xenophon has him make a distinction between those who do evil out of ignorance or due to madness; madmen need to be kept in prison.76 In Plato's Apology Socrates says that if he has harmed anyone, he has done so out of ignorance. Therefore he asks Meletus to instruct him how to improve his ways rather than punish him, since his errors are unintentional.77

In the Euthyphro Socrates gets the righteous gentleman to agree that most people do not argue whether a wrong should be punished, but usually debate whether an action is right or wrong.78 This leads to the question of values. Socrates also discussed the relations of values and the principles of good and evil in the Lysis, although no conclusion was reached.79

In the Theaetetus Socrates declares that the concept of evil is a necessary relative to good, but goodness itself is divine and heavenly. Evil therefore is only found in earthly things. Also those who become most virtuous become most like God. Seeing the value of the good life, Theodorus expresses the hope that evils among mankind will be lessened. He stimulates this response from Socrates:

But it is impossible for evils to be eliminated, Theodorus, for there must always be something opposed to the good. They cannot have their place among the gods, but of necessity they hover around the mortal nature and this earth. Therefore we ought to fly away from earth to heaven as quickly as we can; to fly away is to become like God, as far as this is possible; to become like God is to become just and holy with wisdom. But my good friend, it is not very easy to convince people that they should pursue virtue or avoid vice, not merely that one may seem to be good, which is the reason given by the world, and in my opinion is only the repetition of an old wives' tale. Let us tell the truth, God is never in any way unjust, but is perfectly just, and he among us who is the most just is most like him. Herein is the true cleverness of a man, and also his nothingness and cowardice; for knowing this is wisdom and true virtue, and ignorance of it is folly and manifest vice. All other kinds of seeming cleverness and wisdom, such as in politics and the arts, are coarse and vulgar in comparison.80

Such cleverness is only vanity, for they do not understand the pain of injustice. There are two patterns: the divine which is most blessed, and the godless which is most wretched. Evil men associate with evil, and think these discussions are foolish; but if they are willing to stay in such a conversation, they can be brought to the realization that their arguments are unsatisfactory.81 Discussions on virtue, then, were an important part of Socrates' work. Let us look at the main virtues he examined.

Desire and Self-control
Xenophon describes how Socrates pointed out that desires could lead to slavery if a man allows them to rule him. Gluttony, lechery, drinking, gambling, foolish and costly ambitions, any of these can get hold of a man and force him to give over all his profits to these habits until he becomes old and miserable.82

Socrates also counseled Xenophon and Critobulus against falling into sensual passion. Kissing a pretty face can lead to the end of liberty as one begins to spend his money and time pursuing these pleasures. A kiss can be like a scorpion's sting which injects a poison that is painful and maddening.83 Here Socrates couches his warning in a humorous analogy.

He described envy as having pain at a friend's success, which is clearly irrational, and can only occur in a fool.84 Such an explanation could help a person to see this pattern, and perhaps change it.

In the Phaedrus Socrates distinguishes two principles within man: the natural desire for pleasure, and rational thinking which strives after what is best. When desire irrationally drags one into pleasure, this misrule is called excess. There are many types, such as gluttony which is excessive desire for food.85 In the Republic Socrates explains the difference between necessary and unnecessary desires. Using the same example, the desire to eat is essential to the continuance of life, but it is the luxuries or large amounts which are unnecessary or excessive.86

Uncontrolled desires lead to slavery and are also a characteristic of the tyrannical man. The passionate lusts of the appetites become tyrannical if they are allowed to rule. The person is driven to attempt to fulfill the desires by any means, even vicious ones. Power then can increase the corruption, because circumstances are not as restraining. Ultimately it is the political dictator who can cause the most misery for others and himself.87 Here Socrates portrays the extreme case of vice.

Socrates must have discussed pleasure often, since it is such a strong force for most people. The Philebus is an extensive discussion of the topic. The debate is whether pleasure or wisdom is the good. There are various kinds of pleasure. Pleasure without awareness of it is not really valuable, and a life of wisdom devoid of pleasure is not desirable. Therefore neither alone is sufficient, and it is likely we shall have to mingle them to find the good life. To understand pleasure we must also recognize pain. Pleasure is the restoration of harmony which often occurs after the dissolution of a pain. The soul can also experience pleasure and pain due to expectation in the mind. Desire is the wish to restore the harmony as anticipated by the mind. Since the mind can have true or false opinions in it, desires or pleasures can be true or false. It is possible also to live without pain, which is not necessarily the pleasantest life, since it could be neutral. The greatest pleasures, or the most extreme ones, are the grossest or most physical, such as scratching an itch. Mixed pleasures are of the body and mind, and usually include hope. Then there are pleasures of the mind and emotions such as anger, fear, desire, sorrow, love, emulation, envy, etc. Although these are not physical, they still mix pleasure with pain. The pure pleasures are aesthetic and intellectual, relating to beauty and knowledge. Although they are lesser and more subtle, these are better than the impure pleasures which include some pain. Pleasure and pain are generated out of each other, and are not absolute essences, like the good. Therefore it is absurd to equate the pleasant with the virtuous and the painful with the vicious. Certainly a good man may be experiencing pain without becoming bad due to it!88

A similar but shorter discussion occurs in the Republic. The lover of wisdom (philosopher) has greater experience than either the lover of honor or the lover of wealth, and therefore can get a better perspective on pleasure. Pleasure and pain are relative to each other. Again the lack of pain is not necessarily pleasant. Intellectual things are longer lasting and more true than bodily things; therefore intellectual pleasures are more real than sensual pleasures. Again the sensual pleasures are mixed with more pain. However, both kinds of pleasures are attained to the highest extent when reason and knowledge are guiding. While the tyrant suffers the worst pain, the true philosopher achieves the highest pleasures.89 Such an analysis can be helpful even to those who seek a life of pleasure.

The virtues which restrain and govern the desires for the sake of excellence are self-control and temperance. Xenophon gives us samples of Socrates' discourses on self-control (enkrateia). Socrates asks his friends who they would trust to govern the state, or to educate their children, or to take care of their possessions: a slave of the belly or wine or lust or sleep? If they would not choose such a slave, then they as masters ought to watch to be sure they do not become vicious and harm themselves by stealing or mischief. "Should not every man hold self-control to be the foundation of all virtue, and first establish this firmly in his soul? For can anyone without this learn anything good or practice it in a worthy way? Or what man that is the slave of his pleasures is not in bad shape body and soul alike?"90

Xenophon recalls a conversation with Euthydemus typical of the ones Socrates held to continually remind his friends of self-control as an aid to virtue. Socrates asks him if he values freedom, and then asks if he considers the man free who is ruled by his bodily pleasures. They agree the uncontrolled are the worst slaves since they are ruled by the worst things. Wisdom and prudence are dulled and lost, and the uncontrolled makes bad choices which turn out to be harmful. The uncontrolled do not even experience as much pleasure as those who are able to discipline themselves; they attempt to fulfill their desires so fast that there is no pleasure at all, while those who can wait enjoy greater satisfaction in eating, drinking, sex, and sleeping. The self-controlled also take delight in learning many things useful to their friends and the city. The uncontrolled are like a beast, not caring at all for virtue, but the self-controlled can see what is best and most pleasant, choosing the good and rejecting the bad.91 Here Socrates shows the consequences of the two types of life.

Temperance or self-restraint (sophrosune) is explained by Socrates in the Cratylus as being derived from "salvation" (so) and "wisdom" or "prudence" (phronesis).92 Unfortunately there is no exact English equivalent; it can mean moderation in desires, self-control, temperance, chastity, sobriety, etc. Plato's Charmides is an attempt to define it, but it is far from conclusive. It is certainly not quietness and modesty as Charmides suggests. Neither is it merely doing one's business. It is more than doing good actions, because it requires self-knowledge. In testing self-knowledge as a definition, they decide it must be a science of something, but it cannot be knowledge merely of knowledge. The knowledge needed for happiness is the knowledge of good and evil. Now we are examining wisdom as the science of sciences, but this too fails if it has no practical application as does, for example, medicine, the science of health.93 This is another example of Socrates getting people to think about something and to realize they do not know what it is, as they had thought.

In the Phaedo Socrates explains that many people become temperate and control their passions and appetites in order to get more pleasure out of them. They abstain from some pleasures, because they are overcome by others; in other words, they are temperate for the sake of intemperance. However, true philosophers are temperate in every way for the sake of wisdom and virtue.94 In this case Socrates transcends temperance to move into wisdom which includes temperance.

In the Republic temperance or the control of pleasures and desires is described as a process of self-mastery. Mastery is when the better principle rules over the worse. This is reflected in the aristocratic state as rule by the better.95 Here Socrates describes this virtue on the individual and collective levels.

Again in the Gorgias Socrates suggests to Callicles that "a man should be temperate and master of himself, and ruler of his own pleasures and passions."96 However, Callicles believes that temperance and justice are only practiced out of fear, and that any man who has power would be foolish to be temperate. For Callicles pleasures are the real value of living. Socrates describes intemperance as the annoyance of always trying to fill a leaky vessel. Socrates shows that a man may not have good and evil at the same time, although he can experience pleasure and pain together; therefore good and evil is not the same as pleasure and pain. The good is prior to pleasure, because people seek pleasure and all things because they are good, but goodness is not sought for its pleasure. The assumption here again is that the essential purpose of all actions is for some good. The flatteries or sham arts such as beautification, cookery, sophistry and rhetoric are sought for the pleasures they give the body and soul, but the true arts of gymnastics, medicine, legislation, and justice are practiced for the good of the body and soul. Temperance and justice are aids in being lawful and orderly for the good of the body and soul. Thus the temperate soul is good, and the intemperate is bad.97 Thus Socrates delineates the difference between pleasure and goodness, and how they are expressed in different activities.

Courage
Courage, or literally "manliness," is considered one of the cardinal virtues. However, Socrates often pointed out that truly courageous action depends also on knowledge or wisdom so that the action will be right. In Xenophon Socrates demonstrates this point to Euthydemus and concludes that "those who know how to deal well with terrors and dangers are courageous, and those who are mistaken in this are cowards."98 It follows from this that to some extent courage can be learned. Socrates recognized that natural abilities varied, but he also believed that they could be greatly improved by application. "From this it is clear that all men, whatever their natural gifts, the talented and the dullards alike, must learn and practice that in which they wish to excell."99 Here Socrates is realistic and practical and encouraging.

Most of the Laches is an attempt to define the nature of courage with the help of two famous generals. When Socrates asks what it is, Laches begins with the common understanding that courage is fighting in battle without running away. However, Socrates points out that the Scythian cavalry are very skilled at fighting on the run; besides courage also shows up in perils at sea, in disease, in poverty, or in politics. What quality does courage give in all these cases? Laches then suggests endurance of the soul as its universal nature. Foolish endurance does not seem wise, so Laches qualifies it as wise endurance. However, Socrates suggests cases that indicate to Laches that wisdom usually makes it easier for one to endure, and it appears then as being less courageous than the one who endures without the knowledge. Then Nicias quotes a statement he once heard from Socrates that "every man is good in that in which he is wise, and bad in that in which he is unwise." Therefore he offers the idea that the brave man is wise. However, courage is certainly not all wisdom, such as knowing how to play a musical instrument. Nicias then qualifies it as "the knowledge of that which inspires fear or confidence in war, or in anything." Socrates asks if by defining courage as wisdom, that excludes all animals, even the lion, from being courageous. Laches ridicules such an idea, but Nicias having been educated by sophists makes a distinction between boldness and courageous actions, which are wise actions. Finally Socrates shows that this definition describes all of virtue whereas they had already agreed that courage was only a part of virtue.100 In fact Socrates often ran into this dilemma.

In the Protagoras Socrates holds that the courageous are those who are confident in their knowledge and wisdom.101 In the Phaedo Socrates makes the same point about courage as he did about temperance, that most men are only courageous out of fear of something worse. Only the true philosopher faces death courageously without fear of anything at all.102

In the Republic where the three aspects of the soul are described as the appetites, the passion or spirited, and reason, the virtues corresponding to each of the three are held to be temperance for the appetites, courage for the aggressive spirit, and wisdom for the reason. "He is considered courageous whose spirit retains in pleasure and in pain the commands of reason about what he should or should not fear.... He is temperate who has these same elements in friendly harmony, in whom the one ruling principle of reason and its two subjects are in agreement that reason ought to rule, and do not rebel.... And we call him wise who has in him that small part which rules and proclaims these commands, that part having a knowledge of what is for the interest of each of the three parts and of the whole."103 We see here the interrelation of these virtues and the indispensable role of wisdom.

Knowledge and Wisdom
According to Xenophon, Socrates believed in using human knowledge in those areas which could be reasonably studied and inquired into, such as crafts and arts and sciences. However, in regard to questions which man does not understand, such as future events, he advised his friends to consult the gods through an oracle. "If any man thinks that these matters are wholly within the grasp of the human mind and nothing in them is beyond our reason, that man, he said, is irrational."104 He considered it just as irrational to inquire of an oracle when human reasoning and study could solve the problem.

In fact, in human affairs it is knowledge of how to do something which leads to success in that activity. Socrates explains this to the young Pericles in terms of being a good general, that if he does not have the knowledge needed he seeks out someone with good advice from whom he can learn.105 Experience shows us that any given activity is governed by the one who knows how to do it, while others who do not know will gladly take orders from the knowledgeable one. This is true in government, on a ship, in farming, even in spinning wool where the women govern the men.106 It is interesting to note that in Xenophon's examples it is not abstract knowledge he is talking about but the practical knowledge of how to do something. Plato demonstrates the same point as Socrates shows the young Lysis how even his slaves are trusted by his parents above him in matters which they know better, while he is free and useful in those subjects he had learned, such as reading and writing and music.107

In the Laches Socrates points out that questions ought to be decided by those who know, not be mere majority vote. The opinion of one knowledgeable person may be of more value than the opinions of all the rest.108 Socrates was always ready to take advice from someone who knew.

In the Euthydemus Socrates asks what knowledge we ought to acquire. He answers his own question with the obvious - knowledge which will do us good. Even if we know how to find gold, we would still need to know how to use the gold. Any knowledge, whether of money-making or medicine or any other art which can make something, is not sufficient unless we can use the thing made as well. Even the kingly or political art, although it does use certain things, does not grant every wisdom which is useful to man. Thus the knowledge which benefits by use was not found.109 Yet for Socrates we can see that usefulness was an important criterion for beneficial knowledge.

The Theaetetus is an extended discussion in search of an understanding of what knowledge is. Theaetetus gives examples of the arts, but Socrates wants a definition. Theaetetus suggests that knowledge is perception, the notion of Protagoras that man is the measure of all things. However, Socrates points out the limitations of this subjective relativity, and by using memory shows that knowledge is more than sense perception. Also everyone cannot know, because many people disagree.110 Experts are able to know better, as the wise can measure things more accurately. The soul may perceive through the eyes and ears, but it is also able to think about and combine these perceptions and also grasp ideas directly, such as being, identity, beauty, and the good. Learning occurs through education, and truth is found by reasoning, not by mere sense.

When sense perception was shown not to be knowledge, Theaetetus suggests that knowledge is true opinion. What then is false opinion? This problem they are not able to solve. It cannot be simply confusing perceptions with knowledge, because it is also possible to be wrong in abstract thoughts. It is not possible to know something and not know it at the same time. Since this did not work, they return to examine what it means to know. Using the aviary metaphor they consider it as having and holding knowledge. However, false opinion still confuses the issue, for how can possession of even the wrong knowledge be ignorance? Putting aside false opinion, they go back in search of knowledge. Perhaps it could be true opinion with reasoning. As with letters and syllables, maybe the elements are unknowable, but the combinations are knowable. However, if the letters are unknown, then the syllables become the unknown elements, and if the syllables can be known, then the letters can be known. This gets nowhere. Rational explanation in speech or the enumeration of the parts may indicate knowledge, except these may be done without really knowing. Again this is merely right opinion, even with the recognition of certain differences. The conclusion is that none of their definitions is adequate, but perhaps they are now humbler and better off since they realize they do not consciously know.111 Such a discussion acquaints one with the difficulties which still plague philosophers today.

Usually Socrates was more concerned with self-knowledge than knowledge in the abstract. Once when Phaedrus asked him about a fable and myth, Socrates says that he could probably give a rational explanation for them, but he has no spare time for that. This is the reason:

I am not yet able, in accordance with the Delphic inscription, to know myself; so it seems ridiculous to me, while in this ignorance to consider irrelevant things. Therefore I say farewell to them and accept the customary belief about them, as I was just now saying, and investigate not these things, but myself, to know whether I am a monster more complicated and furious than Typhon or a gentler and simpler creature to whom a divine and quiet destiny has been given by nature.112

Socrates began by examining himself.

He also assisted individuals in looking at themselves, as we have seen in the case of Alcibiades. Alcibiades claimed to have the knowledge he needed, but then Socrates showed him that he neither learned it from someone who knows nor did he discover it himself. His confusion in answering the questions indicates not only his ignorance but also his lack of awareness of his ignorance. This is the most dangerous kind of ignorance, because such a person tends to make mistakes by acting on what he thinks he knows. However, by realizing his ignorance he can quite simply avoid mistakes by not acting.113 This self-knowledge of one's own ignorance could save a person a lot of grief.

When they decide to study to know themselves better, Alcibiades is again shown that he is ignorantly making suggestions on how to improve the city. Socrates suggests that he learn to take care of himself first. Now they must discover what the self is. The one who takes care of things is the user of things, not what is used. Since man takes care not only of his possessions but also of his body, then the self must be the soul of man who uses the body. The soul is the ruling principle, and it is the soul which knows. How then can the soul know itself? Just as the eye must look into the pupil of the eye to see itself, so the soul must examine its virtue which resembles the divine wisdom. Those who are ignorant of themselves will not understand human affairs and will fail and be miserable. He who knows the virtue of the soul will act wisely and justly according to the will of God as he looks in the divine mirror to know himself and his own good.114 If this is true, and it certainly seems so to this writer, then is not this process of self-awareness the key to living well?

The opposite of self-knowledge is self-deception. In the Philebus Socrates lists three common areas in which ignorance of self appears - in regard to one's money, one's physical looks, and one's wisdom and virtue. Many people tend to be conceited and consider themselves richer, better looking, and wiser than they are. Of these those with little or no power are merely ridiculous, but the powerful can do great harm to others.115 Here Socrates points out the most common pitfalls for individuals and the dangers to mankind.

Xenophon tells how Socrates emphasized the importance for a tyrant to take good advice, because if he does not the resulting mistake will not go unpunished. Nor could a tyrant kill a loyal subject without suffering some loss.116 Here again the greater the power is, the greater is the need for self-knowledge and wisdom.

Diogenes Laertius tells how Socrates used to encourage people to study and improve themselves. He marveled that sculptors could work so hard to make a block of marble perfectly resemble a man, but would not care at all whether they themselves turned out to be blockheads. To the young he recommended the use of a mirror so that the handsome might acquire the corresponding conduct, and the ugly might conceal their defects by education.117

Among the many occasions Xenophon described of Socrates helping individuals to know themselves is the one where he advised Charmides to go into politics because his capabilities were needed. Socrates challenges him that it would be cowardly for him to shrink from serving the state when he had the ability. Socrates has observed Charmides giving good advice to politicians and also correct criticism. However, Charmides fears he will be timid and shy before a large audience, but Socrates assures him that they are far more ignorant than he is. Socrates concludes his talk with this exhortation:

My good man, don't be ignorant of yourself; don't fall into the common error. For many are in such a hurry to pry into other people's business that they never turn to examining themselves. Don't refuse to face this duty then; make more serious effort to pay attention to yourself, and don't neglect public affairs if you have the ability to improve them. If they go well, not only the citizens, but your friends and you yourself will benefit at least as much as they will.118

Many who are ambitious are better off held back from public life, but in this case Socrates felt the need to urge his friend into government.

Xenophon also explains how Socrates would discourage pretense to knowledge or ability among his friends by showing what happens to impostures. First they must try to gain the appearance of a musician or general or whatever, which is expensive, burdensome, unprofitable, and disgraceful. If the person is exposed he becomes ridiculous, and if he succeeds in gaining a position such as piloting a ship or commanding an army, the results can be disastrous, bringing ruin and disgrace. Therefore even a reputation for virtue which goes beyond one's abilities can disappoint expectations.119 Thus by self-knowledge and true humility a person could avoid many problems.

Xenophon shows Socrates making a connection between wisdom and knowledge. A man is only wise in what he knows. Since it is impossible for a man to know everything, there can be no all-wise man.120 This enables us to understand Socrates' humility in not claiming to be wise.

Wisdom requires knowledge, but knowledge of what? Xenophon states that Socrates made no distinction between wisdom and prudence (temperance), and that the wise and prudent man "knows and practices what is beautiful and good, knows and avoids what is shameful." Here wisdom implies the unification of knowledge and action. When Socrates is asked the obvious question about those who know what they ought to do and yet do the opposite, whether they are both wise and self-controlled, he replied, "No, rather, they are unwise and uncontrolled. For I think that all have a choice between various courses, and they do the things which they think are most advantageous to them. Therefore I believe that those who do not act correctly are neither wise nor prudent."121 The obvious solution then is to develop wisdom; but it must be practiced as well as understood, or it is not truly wisdom.

According to Xenophon, Socrates considered justice and all the other virtues to be wisdom, and again he relates it to action and knowledge of the ideals of beauty and goodness. "For just actions and all forms of virtuous activity are beautiful and good. He who knows the beautiful and good will never choose anything else."122 This is knowledge in its strongest sense, not thinking, nor thinking one knows, but knowledge verified by action. Socrates described madness as the opposite of wisdom, although ignorance was not considered exactly the same. Madness was held to be an extreme case, as love is a strong desire, where someone was mistaken in a matter of common knowledge. However, "not to know yourself, and to assume and think that you know what you do not, he put next to madness."123

Plato also portrays Socrates giving a pragmatic definition of wisdom. In the splendid exhortation Socrates demonstrates in the Euthydemus, Socrates shows how wisdom is the greatest good, because it causes success in every action. Any other thing which is considered good may be harmful if it is not used wisely, but wisdom gives us the right use of all things. To be able to use everything correctly and gain success leads to happiness. Socrates concludes, "Since everyone desires happiness, and we have shown that this comes from using things, and using them correctly, and the greatest correctness and good fortune is provided by knowledge, the inference is that everyone ought to prepare himself in every way to become as wise as he can."124 Since life consists of using things, Socrates has shown that wisdom is helpful in everything.

Plato in the Apology also shows Socrates admitting that human wisdom is worthy little or nothing compared to the true wisdom of God.125 Even so, human wisdom is still better than ignorance. In the Crito Socrates explains to his friend that he must follow the opinion of the wise rather than public opinion. Therefore Socrates uses his reasoning based on the good life as his chief value to discover the wisest and just action.126

Finally in the Phaedo the proposition that the soul is immortal implies that wisdom can be valuable even beyond this life. In the Euthydemus Socrates had said, "If there were a knowledge which was able to make men immortal without knowing how to use that immortality, there would be no advantage in it."127 Now Socrates shows that wisdom itself is the knowledge which benefits the soul not only in this life and in this world, but also in the next world and in future lives. In fact if the soul is eternal, then eventually everyone must attain wisdom and goodness!

My friends, it is right to understand that if the soul is immortal, we should care for it, not only in respect to this time which we call life, but in respect to all time; the danger now seems terrible, if we neglect it. For if death was an escape from everything, it would be a bargain to the wicked when they die and are released from the body and the wickedness with the soul. But now since being is shown to be immortal, there is no escape or salvation from evil except to become as good and wise as possible. For the soul takes nothing into the other world except its education and upbringing, which are said to greatly benefit or injure the departed from the very beginning of his journey there.128

The orderly and wise soul fares much better in following its guiding spirit and in understanding its circumstances, while the soul which desires the body wanders in the lower more visible realms until after much resistance it is forcefully led away by its guide.129 The choices of future lifetimes on earth are also determined by the wisdom of the soul. The value of developing wisdom in terms of all the future consequences can be great indeed!
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 116 发表于: 2009-03-15
SOCRATES
Content and Topics
(Continued)
Traditional Subjects
Politics
Virtue
Desires and Self-control
Courage
Knowledge and Wisdom
Justice
Holiness
Friendship and Love
The Philosopher
The Good
Immortality of the Soul
This chapter has been published in the book CONFUCIUS AND SOCRATES Teaching Wisdom. For ordering information, please click here.

Justice
Socrates often discussed the topic of justice. Xenophon recollected a long conversation he had with Hippias on justice in which Hippias commented that Socrates was still talking about the same old things. Hippias boasted that he could say something new about justice, and Socrates was eager to hear. However, Hippias complained that Socrates was always questioning others, and he challenged him to give his own account. Socrates began by mentioning that his own deeds are just, but Hippias pinned him down to a definition. Socrates declared, "What is lawful is just."130 The discussion showed that this means the laws made by the citizens as covenants or agreements with each other, even though some break them. The just person who obeys these laws and keeps one's agreements is the most trustworthy. However, Socrates did not limit justice to public laws, but he included also "unwritten laws," which must not have been made by people because they are shared by various cultures which speak different languages. Hippias suggested that God made these laws for people, for the first one is to reverence the gods. Socrates added the duty of honoring one's parents and the prohibition against incest. Hippias disagreed with the latter because he found that some transgress it. However, Socrates pointed out that those who did could not escape punishment. Another duty, that of returning benefits, was also broken, but such people suffer the gradual loss of friends. In conclusion, Socrates suggested that the gods ordained what is just, and therefore even the gods "accept the identification of the just and the lawful."131 Apparently Socrates taught the universal principle of law based on divine will as the best system for justice.

In going over Socrates' definitions, Xenophon again indicated that Socrates held that the just are those who know what is lawful and do it.132 As with wisdom, we see here the unification of knowledge and action.

Defending himself before the jury in Plato's Defense of Socrates, Socrates declared that justice is more important than death, and he cited the case of Achilles. Socrates had a deep conviction in the ultimate justice of life as indicated by his statement: "I believe it is not God's will that a better person be injured by a worse."133 Socrates referred here to a substantial injury to one's soul, not mere loss of civil rights, banishment, or even death. Rather he warned his accusers that the law of justice would bring punishment upon them for condemning an innocent man.

Socrates also refused to bring in his family to make an emotional plea because it would be an attempt to sway the judges to grant favors. This is not the duty of a good judge; instead he exhorted them to judge according to the laws.134 In the Crito he maintained his conviction that it is just and best to obey the law even though it meant his own extinction.135 Socrates discussed justice in situations where others, such as Crito, might have thought other considerations were more important, because for Socrates justice was apparently most important.

In the Gorgias Socrates discussed justice in relation to rhetoric, which only attempts to make things appear just. Socrates took the martyr's position that it is better to suffer injustice than to do it; for doing injustice injures the soul, while suffering injustice purifies it. Socrates believed that all happiness consists of education and justice. He showed that it is actually worse for the wrong-doer not to be punished, because punishment is the justice which cures the soul. The soul is more valuable than the body; therefore keeping it in balance through justice is more important than physical pain and will lead to true happiness. Justice prevents wrong-doing from becoming a chronic cancer of the soul. The best use of rhetoric, then, is to reveal to a person one's own injustice so that it may be quickly corrected.136

If virtue is happiness, and vice is misery, then the greatest evil that can happen to someone is to do wrong and not be corrected for it by punishment. Thus it is better to suffer wrong than to do wrong. Ultimately this love of goodness can transcend even the fear of death.137 Socrates concluded the discussion with an account of the judgment which occurs after death when the soul has departed from the body. The judges in the other world pay no attention to what the body had been like or the social status, but they look only at the quality of the soul and its actions. The wicked are sent to be punished in Tartarus, and the virtuous go to the Islands of the Blessed.138 This was Socrates' way of explaining that ultimately the gods are just, and every soul gets its due.

The Republic began as an investigation of what justice is. The definitions of Simonides that justice is paying one's debts and being truthful were refuted by Socrates by means of exceptional cases, though a better dialectician might have been able to make the distinctions necessary to rescue these definitions. Socrates, however, was clearing the way for a more comprehensive search. He also refuted the common idea that justice is to benefit one's friends and harm one's enemies by showing it is unjust to injure anyone.139

Socrates refuted Thrasymachus' notion that injustice is better than justice by describing how complete injustice arouses hatred and is totally incompetent; even a gang of thieves has to be somewhat fair and cooperative among themselves in order to be successful. On the other hand, "justice brings oneness of mind and love." The just are wiser, better, and more capable of action.140 Socrates made it clear that justice is better than injustice, but he was not yet satisfied that he knew what justice is.

Next Glaucon asked Socrates to show that justice is not only good for its consequences such as rewards and reputation but is good for itself alone even without these other things. Socrates was pleased to accept the challenge, as he was delighted to discuss justice over and over.141 The extended discussions in the Republic have been presented in other places. Let us note here his description of the good judge and the conclusions Socrates drew about justice. The training of the judge is not exactly analogous to the training of the physician. The physician benefits from having experience oneself with diseases, but it is better for the judge to keep his soul pure of moral corruption. The judge should not know evil from practice but from long observation of the evil nature in others.142 For Socrates it was fundamental that a judge be a good person.

Finally when Socrates had shown that the soul as akin to the eternal and divine is in its best condition by itself when it is virtuous and just, the challenge had been answered. Then the rewards could be added also. The gods love those who are just; in the long run the just fare better, and the unjust end up suffering. Again Socrates capped his discussion of justice with a tale of the other world and the rewards and purgations which follow the judgment after death.143 From the perspective of the soul, to be just is to be blessed, and to be unjust is to suffer.

Holiness
In Xenophon, Socrates defined piety or holiness as knowing how to worship the gods lawfully.144 Thus piety is closely analogous to justice, which relates to what is lawful concerning people.

Xenophon also recorded extensive conversations Socrates had to increase his companions' awareness of God's blessings in order to encourage them to be pious. In one Socrates asked Euthydemus about the care the gods have taken to provide people with everything they need. They have given light to see by, night for a time of rest, stars to mark the night, and the moon also to define the month. The earth yields food in appropriate seasons; water nourishes our bodies; and because so much is needed, it is plentiful. Fire is useful against cold and darkness. The sun gradually gets warmer and colder, but neither extreme is too great. Euthydemus was able to see the divine design and the loving kindness of the gods, but he wondered also that the lower animals also enjoy these blessings. Socrates then pointed out how goats, sheep, horses, oxen, asses, and other animals are valuable to people for food and commerce and work. They considered how the gods have endowed people with senses adapted for various perceptions; also they have granted the faculty of reasoning and memory so that we can enjoy the good and eliminate the bad. We can express and communicate and share with each other, enacting laws and administering states. Although humans cannot see the future, the gods reveal issues through divination to those who inquire. At this point Euthydemus noted Socrates' particular divine sign as a special blessing.145 Then Socrates explained the invisibility and the omnipresence of God.

That I tell the truth you will know if,
instead of waiting to see the physical forms of the gods,
you are satisfied to praise and worship them
by seeing their works.
Notice that the gods themselves demonstrate this,
for when they give good things to us,
none of them ever appears before us gift in hand;
and especially the one who coordinates
and holds together the universe
in which all things are beautiful and good,
and who always presents them fresh
and sound and ageless to be used,
and quicker than thought serves unerringly,
that one is seen in the greatest works,
and yet is unseen by us in the managing of them.
Notice that even the sun, who seems to reveal himself to all,
does not allow man to see him closely,
but if anyone attempts to look recklessly at him,
one's eyes are blinded.
Also the servants of the gods you will find are invisible;
for it is evident that the thunderbolt is hurled from above
and that it conquers all wherever it falls,
but is not seen either coming or striking or going;
and the winds themselves are not seen;
yet what they do is clear to us, and we perceive their approach.
In addition the soul of man,
which more than anything else human partakes of God,
reigns manifestly within us, and yet is itself unseen.

Understanding this, we should not disdain the unseen;
but since by close examination we know their power,
we ought to honor the spiritual.146

Euthydemus questioned how he could ever benefit God, but Socrates advised him to follow the counsel of the Delphic god to obey the laws of the state. He encouraged Euthydemus to honor the gods in this way as strictly as he could so that he could receive the greatest benefits.147 In such a comprehensive explanation Socrates indicated to his listener how many blessings he had for which he should be grateful.

In another conversation with Aristodemus, Socrates showed that the design of creation indicates the purpose of a creative God. When Socrates noticed that Aristodemus the dwarf, as he was called, did not use prayer or divination and mocked those who did, Socrates asked him if he admired any human beings for their wisdom. Aristodemus named Homer, Sophocles, and the outstanding sculptor and painter of his time. Socrates asked him to compare the phantoms they created to living, intelligent, and active beings. Although he admired living beings more by far, he assumed that they were created by chance. Socrates asked if the creatures that serve a useful purpose were more likely to be the result of chance or design. He then pointed out how various aspects of man are useful in specific ways. We have senses to perceive-eyes to see visible objects, ears to hear sounds. What value would odors have if we could not smell with our nostrils? Similarly with tastes, what if we had no tongue to discriminate sweet from bitter and others? The eyeballs, being soft, are protected behind eyelids which open and close like doors, so we can see or sleep. Eyelashes filter the winds, and eyebrows keep forehead perspiration from falling in the eyes. The ears catch all sounds, but they are not choked with them. The front teeth are adapted to biting off, while the molars can do the grinding and chewing. The mouth is conveniently placed next to the nostrils and eyes, but the ducts of elimination which release the unpleasant matter are placed far away from the senses. Aristodemus was beginning to see the handiwork of a wise and loving creator.148

Also there is the natural desire to beget children, the mother's spontaneous care of the baby, and the child's will to live and fear of death. Yet how much wisdom can a person have in a mere speck of all the earth and a mere drop of all the water that one's body contains? As for one's mind which is weightless, by what lucky accident did one snap it up, and are the orderly ranks of all the huge masses that are infinite in number caused by some kind of an absurdity? Aristodemus was still in doubt because he did not see the master hand. Socrates reminded him that he did not see his own soul either; but it masters his body. Certainly his own life is guided by design and not chance.149

At this point Aristodemus complained that spirit is too great to need his service; but Socrates declared that because it serves him, it is worthy of honor. To show that man has special favor from the gods, Socrates delineated how man is the only creature to stand upright with a wide range of vision; we are endowed with hands, which are particularly useful, and with a tongue, which can articulate the voice and express our wishes to each other. Sex is not limited by a certain season but only by old age. Man has the noblest soul, which can understand the gods who set in order the universe; only humans worship the gods. Man provides against hunger and thirst, cold and heat, relieves sickness and promotes health, acquires knowledge by work, and remembers accurately all that is heard, seen, or learned. Compared to other animals, people live like gods, by nature without equal in body or soul. The gods have given man the two most precious gifts; reason for the soul and hands for the body.150

Next Aristodemus wanted the gods to send counselors with specific advice so that he could believe. Socrates mentioned how the Athenians used divination and how portents were sent to all the world. Would God have put the belief in man that they can help or harm if they did not have the power? Would not man throughout all the ages have detected the fraud?

Do you not see that the wisest and most enduring
of human institutions, cities, and nations, are most god-fearing,
and that the most thoughtful period of life is the most religious?
Be well assured, my good friend, that the mind within you
directs your body according to its will;
and equally you must think that Thought
indwelling in the Universal disposes all things
according to its pleasure.
For think not that your eye can travel over several miles
and yet God's eye cannot see the whole world at once;
that your soul can ponder on things in Egypt and in Sicily,
and God's thought is not sufficient
to take care of the whole world at once.
But just as by serving people you find out
who is willing to serve you in return,
by being kind who will be kind to you in return,
and by taking counsel, discover the masters of thought,
so test the gods by serving them,
and see whether they intend to counsel you
in matters hidden from man.
Then you will know that this is the greatness
and this is the nature of the deity
that it sees all things and hears all things,
and is present everywhere and takes care of everything.151

Such explanations by Socrates enabled some skeptics to see a larger and more coherent picture of man's place in the universe and our relationship to the Creator.

When someone needed help that was beyond the ability of human wisdom, then Socrates recommended that the person consult the gods through divination as a means of divine guidance and counsel.152

Plato's Euthyphro was an unsuccessful attempt to define holiness or piety. Here we see Socrates at work refuting a man who claimed to be pious, but whose action of prosecuting his father for murder because he allowed a murdering servant to die (while he consulted a diviner what to do), leaves us with serious doubts as to Euthyphro's piety. It turned out that none of his definitions of piety held up.153 Perhaps in this case the man's actions spoke louder than his words.

Friendship and Love
Socrates used the term philos to mean love in the sense of a friend and Eros as the god of Love and Desire. Xenophon recorded several conversations on friendship. Socrates believed that the best of all possessions was a sincere and good friend. Yet most people are more careless with their friends than they are with their servants or their physical possessions. If a servant is ill, they take better care of him than they would a friend; and people are usually much better at listing their possessions than the names of their friends. Even so, a good friend is more loyal and helpful in watching one's private fortune and public career, in contributing, rescuing from trouble, sharing expenses, defending one's position, celebrating success, and helping up after a fall.154

Socrates was not afraid to put someone on the spot so that he might fulfill the obligation of his friendship. Once when Antisthenes had been neglecting his poverty-stricken friend, Socrates asked him in the presence of his friend, how much value in money Antisthenes placed on his different friendships.155 Such a conversation was obviously designed to stir the man into action on behalf of his friend.

In a discussion with Critobulus, Socrates indicated how to test for the qualities of friendship. The slave of eating and drinking, lust, sleep, or idleness cannot do what he should for himself or his friend. Also the spendthrift or the stingy and selfish business person offers little in friendship. The quarrelsome person makes too many enemies, and the one who receives favors without giving anything in return does not win friendship either. Socrates suggested,

We shall look for one who controls his indulgence
in the pleasures of the body,
who is truly hospitable and fair in his dealings
and eager to do as much for his benefactors
as he receives from them, so that he is worth knowing.156

To test these qualities, Socrates recommended that they look at the person's works to see if they were good and beautiful, just as they would look at the works of a sculptor or examine how an owner of horses treated his animals.157

At this point Critobulus asked Socrates how he could go about winning a friend. As usual Socrates first suggested that they ask for the guidance of the gods in choosing the prospective friend. Rather than hunting the person like an enemy or slave, Socrates mentioned that there are charms that can be sung, as the Sirens put a spell on Odysseus. This charm consisted of praising the person on one's good points. Of course to make good friends, one must be a good and helpful person. However, many people and states also attempt to do good and avoid evil, but they quarrel and treat others harshly as they do so. When such rogues fight with each other for the leadership of states, the friendly elements in people work together in parties; but the hostile elements become angry, fight jealously, and take sides. Some, then, seek friends in politics so that they can win honor, exercise power over others, and live in luxury; these are bound to be unjust, unscrupulous, and incapable of unity. The true gentleman, however, seeks to help his friends in a just cause so that they will not be the victims of injustice; he will be most able to benefit his country. It is preferable to show kindness to the best. Therefore, Critobulus ought to strive to be good and go after his gentleman. Socrates offered to assist him by telling the gentleman honestly about Critobulus and how he feels toward the man and the importance he places on friendship. However, Critobulus must study and practice virtue so that he will be thought good.158 Thus a discussion of friendship became an exhortation to become a better person.

Xenophon recorded how Socrates and his friends went to see the beautiful woman of pleasure, Theodote. After pointing out how they benefit her by looking at her beauty and becoming her admirers, Socrates gave her advice how she could be successful in obtaining friends. What she needed was an agent, who like a hound, would track down and find rich men who would desire her company. Then she could trap them by the net of her body maneuvered sensitively by the soul. However, she must not grant her favors too readily, but only when the man's desire was peaked. She asked Socrates to become her partner, and he agreed, provided that she came to him as did the others such as Apollodorus, Antisthenes, Cebes, and Simmias.159 Leave it to Socrates to get the courtesan running after him!

Plato dealt with the theme of friendship in the Lysis. First Socrates showed Hippothales how he should humble his friend Lysis by demonstrating that he needed to learn. In this dialog Socrates declared that he had always wanted a good friend, but he had never been able to find one. They argued about whether the lover or the beloved or both were the friends. Friendship appears to require that love is given and returned, but through examples of a love-hate relation-ship Socrates confused his listeners into believing that neither the lover nor the beloved nor both were really friends. Similar confusion surrounded the discussion of the like and unlike and whether the good or the evil loves the good. That good is loved for the sake of evil is only a relative answer and not an ultimate solution. Congeniality appeared to be a factor in the attraction of friendship, but this appeared to contradict the idea that the like is useless to the like.160 The discussion had no solid conclusion at all and seemed to have the main purpose of stimulating the young men to think about these issues without giving them the final answers.

Love in the erotic sense was the only subject Socrates claimed to understand.161 In his Symposium, which shows a knowledge of Plato's Symposium, Xenophon included a speech by Socrates on why spiritual love and friendship are better than physical and sexual love. Socrates began by observing that Love is enthroned in the heart of man as a mighty god, and all of them are influenced by love. He made a distinction between the Aphrodite that is Heavenly, which represents spiritual love, friendship and the beauty of goodness, and the Vulgar Aphrodite of carnal love. Hermogenes who was seeking virtue commented how Socrates was educating Callias toward the ideal by praising his noble conduct.

Socrates explained why the spiritual love is better than the carnal. The lusts of the body care only that they are temporarily satisfied and fade away as youthful beauty passes with age, but the soul becomes increasingly lovable as it progresses toward wisdom. Physical love is the gratification of an appetite, but the spiritual is a more enduring goodness. Returning spiritual love is more reasonable because one is being recognized as a pattern of the gentleman (beautiful and good), which does not alter when the physical appearance changes. Spiritual love begets a mutual trust, happy friendship, and a sense of unity and sharing. However, there is little to lead a person to return the love which is based only on the flesh; the object of such love often does not share the same passion and may be ashamed of the relationship. Socrates used the analogy of a farm. Physical love is like renting a farm to get as much harvest as one can over a short period of time, while spiritual love is like owning the farm and really taking care of it and seeing that it is improved. Spiritual love also stimulates one to practice virtue oneself, so that one's beloved will become self-controlled and honorable. Socrates then cited examples from myth, legend, and recent history of gods and people who demonstrated the importance and value of friendship and spiritual love.162 Here Xenophon portrayed Socrates explaining the common sense differences of the two qualities of love.

In Plato's Symposium Socrates moved into a more philosophic explanation of cosmic love. Instead of defining Love as a thing in one place or another, Socrates described Love as a moving energy which serves as a mean, a kind of link or bridge, between opposites such as good and evil, spirit and matter, gods and people, etc. He did this by first examining Eros as a primordial or cosmic desire which implies a movement toward something rather than a possession of something. Love is not the beautiful and good, but what moves us toward them. Socrates confessed that he learned these things from the mysterious Diotima. Love is a spirit which moves between the gods and humans, the offspring of the opposites Plenty and Poverty. Love moves toward wisdom and beauty and goodness. The possession of these is happiness, and love is what motivates people to give birth in beauty to these ideals. Why does love seek generation? According to Diotima, it is so that the possession of the good will be lasting, the ultimate being eternal. Therefore love desires immortality. Love seeks immortality by means of physical procreation, fame, and virtuous actions. Ultimately love transcends the individual and particular and moves into universal truth and the ideals of beauty and goodness. By this process of spiritual loving, one moves from the earthly to the heavenly and divine. The truly virtuous person then becomes the friend of God and immortal.163 Here Socrates' description of love still leads to the spiritual, but he took his listeners through a process which could move and raise their consciousness.

Love is also described by Socrates in the Phaedrus as a divine madness. This metaphorical description of love was described in the previous chapter. Here again love is seen as a spiritual quality caused by divine inspiration.

The Philosopher
In addition to discussing in a philosophic manner various themes, Socrates occasionally turned his attention to the role of the philosopher, his nature and methods, and what education would be most appropriate for that. In Plato's Sophist the philosopher is called divine and is said by Socrates to appear in many disguises as they visit mankind "beholding from above the life of those below."164 How are philosophers able to get this divine perspective on life? In the Theaetetus Socrates compared his style of life to the lawyer who was always busy in the law courts trying to devise clever and crooked arguments to win his case. In contrast, the philosopher lives a simple life unconcerned with daily business or reputation. That one appears awkward and ignorant of the particular details and is usually laughed at by the general public. However, one uses his liberty and leisure to study the true essences of what is man and justice and government and happiness, and how they are attained.165 The philosophers are the initiated who understand the invisible essences, which are so important in the good life. Earlier in the same dialog Socrates commented, "The uninitiated are those who believe in nothing except what they can grasp in their hands, and who deny the existence of actions and generation and all that is invisible."166

One of the prime requisites of the philosopher, then, is to recognize and work with abstract ideas. Socrates was portrayed by Plato as being concerned with abstract ideas and their relation to concrete objects from the time of his youth when he debated with Zeno and Parmenides.167 In the Phaedo Socrates made extensive use of abstract ideas and the doctrine of recollection which supports the theory that the soul always has the ability to know what the ideas are. Socrates pointed out that the ideas are more perfect than the things we perceive through the senses. For example, we can have an idea of perfect equality in our mind, but we could not find two material objects, such as wood or stone, which are exactly equal. Objects change, but the idea of equality is always the same. Therefore, the ideas are enduring and may have been known to our souls before.168 The philosopher is concerned not only with the eternal ideas but also with the purity of the soul itself which knows those ideas. Although the soul is unseen and intangible, it is lasting, true being. Therefore the philosopher cares more for the soul which is unchanging than for the body which is corruptible and mortal. The philosopher keeps oneself as clear as one can from the pleasures and pains of the body; rather one works to liberate the soul from these chains to the body.169 Finally Socrates expounded upon the idea he discovered in Anaxagoras that mind is the cause of everything. Man's actions are purposeful focuses on the causes in life rather than on the effects and results.170 If we are to change the pattern of our life experience, then we must examine and improve the real causes and origins of our actions.

In the Republic Socrates discussed the activities and education of the philosopher. He complained that philosophy had been misunderstood because of the superficial ways it was being practiced haphazardly. Some learned a little bit about argument and entered into controversies to display their skill at refutation without having any true understanding of the issues. Philosophy also got a bad name from those who compared and criticized persons instead of examining the immutable principles and the divine order for the best human society.171

To educate the philosopher kings, Socrates recommended much more than music and gymnastics. The candidates for the highest responsibility must study arithmetic, as numbers and mathematical concepts are the origin of the intelligible things. This is to be followed by geometry and its practical application, astronomy, and solid geometry of the three dimensions. As these are visual, the auditory is to be studied through harmonics. Then these subjects are to be correlated with each other, and the process of dialectic begins. Dialectic is pure reasoning and is concerned with first principles, inquiry, and the relationships of concepts. Ultimately everything is to be related to the good, for it is the central sun of the intelligible world; in other words, all thought and actions are to be good. The characteristics needed for this education are intelligence, memory, physical and intellectual discipline, industriousness, love of truth, and the virtues of self-control, courage, greatness, and others. None of these studies should be forced on the youth, but they should learn them by play. At age twenty the best will be selected to study for ten years the relationships between the various sciences. Again at thirty the most promising will be selected to study philosophy for five years. Their education is not complete until they spend fifteen more years in practical experience handling offices of the state. Finally after fifty they will spend their time focusing on the light of the absolute good as they advise the state according to the divine pattern.172 This may be a plan for an ideal state, but the suggestions Socrates made could still be pursued by an individual.

The relationship between the abstractions learned in arithmetic and the higher dialectic was also discussed by Socrates in the Philebus. Here the distinction was made between an impure science and a pure science pursued by philosophers for the sake of perfect accuracy and truth. The pure science of dialectic deals with the eternal and unchangeable realities which are the clearest truth. Wisdom, then, is the contemplation of true being.173 Thus dialectic leads one toward the higher realities. In the Phaedrus also Socrates stated that those who employ the dialectic of discerning the true nature of things based on the first principles of justice and goodness and beauty are worthy of being called lovers of wisdom, or philosophers.174 Thus Socrates described the high art of the philosopher.

The Good
The constant reference to the good is the cornerstone of the dialectical process. In the Philebus Socrates and his companions were seeking the good life. They decided they must mix some pleasures as are necessary with wisdom and practical knowledge. However, they eliminated the impure pleasures that are not needed in the experience of life. The ideals of beauty and truth were found to be indispensable to the good life, and balance and appropriateness the qualities which lead to these. Fitness and harmonious proportion were then followed by wisdom, the sciences and arts, and finally the pure pleasures as the essential characteristics of the good life.175 The good, along with the ideals of beauty and truth, served as the beacon light to qualify and evaluate all of the choices and guidelines of living.

The good was described in the Republic through the metaphor of the sun and the allegory of the cave as being the transcendent spiritual reality which illuminates all intelligence and knowing; it is beyond even the ideals and is the source of being. It is the center of the universe and the perfect guide as the giver of light to the enlightened soul who has traveled beyond the world of shadows. When the liberated soul returns to the reflected world of the prisoners, one must always keep one's vision focused on the good.176 Socrates used the good as the focus of spiritual reality; but by using this abstract term instead of God or Spirit, the continual emphasis and reminder is on its practical use, as in good thoughts, good actions, good whatever.

Xenophon had Socrates define both the good and the beautiful simply as what is useful.177 Also in the Greater Hippias attributed to Plato, the beautiful was looked at in terms of being appropriate, useful, and beneficial. Beauty is also considered as pleasing or enjoyable in sight or hearing; beauty then becomes a kind of beneficial pleasure.178 Here we see a similarity to the conclusions of the Philebus, and the close relation between the good and this ideal of beauty.

Socrates was wary of being led astray in an argument about the application of these concepts. Xenophon recorded how Aristippus attempted to trip him up by asking if he knew of anything good. Socrates carefully asked if he meant good for a certain purpose, for anything could be good for one thing and bad for something else. The same is true of whether something is considered beautiful or not; it depends on its function or purpose. Socrates concluded, "For all things are good and beautiful in relation to those purposes for which they are well adapted, bad and ugly in relation to these for which they are ill adapted."179 Discussion of abstractions is one thing; but when applying them to particular situations, one must be specific and qualifying.

Once when someone asked Socrates what was the best pursuit for a person, he replied, "Doing well." The person wondered whether he meant the pursuit of good luck. Socrates explained that luck and doing are at opposite extremes. Luck happens without effort, but doing something well follows from study and practice. "The best people and those who are beloved of God are those who do well; if it is farming, as good farmers; if medicine, as good doctors; if politics, as good politicians. Whoever does nothing well is neither useful in any way nor beloved of God."180 The highest principles are ultimately the most simple, and Xenophon gave it to us from Socrates as practical common sense.

Immortality of the Soul
Most of the discussions by Socrates on the immortality of the soul are found in the works of Plato. However, Xenophon did indicate that Socrates was aware that the soul leaves the body at death. "As soon as the soul, the only seat of intelligence, is gone out of a person, we carry out the body and hide it in the tomb."181 Xenophon seemed to be more concerned with the practicalities of this life, rather than with eternity.

In public Socrates spoke about death in such a way as not to offend the uninitiated. In Plato's Defense of Socrates he presented his audience with two alternatives. Either death is the end of consciousness, a nothingness, or dreamless sleep; or death begins the migration of the soul to the other world where one may visit old friends and the souls of past history. In either case, death is not bad, but a blessing.182 Because his trial was not the time or place to instruct people concerning the true nature of the soul, he simply presented two reasonable choices, reminding them that although he went to die and they to live, only God knows which is better.

In more intimate conversations Socrates presented many theories concerning the soul. In the Philebus Socrates declared that the soul which organizes and heals the body and contains the sum of all wisdom must be derived from the universal intelligence, which wisely and justly arranges all creation. Wisdom and intellect come from the soul, which is the cause of all things.183 This idea that soul and mind are the ordering principle of all things was also echoed in the Cratylus where the soul was also identified as the source of life and power of the breath in the body.184

In the Meno Socrates advocated that the soul is immortal and knows everything from eternity. It is born many times, and education is the process of awakening the knowledge inherent in the soul from before birth.185 The ability of the soul to recognize truth within itself when it sees it out in the world demonstrates this principle that the soul is the eternal knower.

Several characteristics of the soul were described by Socrates in the Philebus. Before going into a figure, Socrates used transcendental logic to prove that the soul as the self-moving principle must be immortal. The logic is transcendental because it deals with the eternal as that which has no beginning and yet is the beginning of all.

Every soul is immortal, for the ever-moving is immortal;
but what moves another or is moved by another,
ceasing to move ceases to have life.
Only the self-moving which never leaves itself,
never ceases to move, and this is also the source
and beginning of motion for all other things which move.
The beginning is unbegotten,
for everything which is begotten has a beginning,
but the beginning is not begotten from anything;
for if the beginning were begotten from anything,
then the begotten would not come from the beginning.
Since the beginning is unbegotten, it must also be indestructible;
for if the beginning were destroyed,
it could never be begotten from anything nor anything else from it,
since all things must come from the beginning.
Thus the self-moving is the beginning of motion.
This can be neither destroyed nor begotten,
or else the whole heaven and all of creation would collapse
and stop and never again have motion or birth.
But the self-moving has been shown to be immortal,
and one who says that this self-motion is the essence
and the very idea of the soul will not be disgraced.
For every body which is moved from without is soulless,
but that which is moved from within itself is the nature of the soul.
And if this is true, that nothing else but the soul moves itself,
then the soul must necessarily be unbegotten and immortal.186

Such an argument shows how the soul transcends the limitations of time and space.

In the figure of the chariot and the pair of winged horses, Socrates described the ability of the soul to transcend into the heavenly worlds provided the charioteer can correctly guide the horses. In the higher realms the soul can follow after various of the divine patterns as symbolized by the different gods and goddesses. It is in these higher realms where the soul perceives the eternal truths. The souls which lose their wings of transcendence fall down to earth and reincarnate in various types of human experience. The philosophers are the ones working to grow back their wings by studying universal truths. Many people seek out beauty in an attempt to re-capture the original beatific vision of the light experienced before the soul became imprisoned in a body. This is why people experience ecstasy when they find some earthly beauty which in some way approaches the divine; this experience is called love.187

The souls on earth still follow the pattern of their god. The good and bad horses represent the two aspects of character which can be virtuous and modest or emotionally unrestrained. If by the charioteer's efforts the passion can be moderated into friendship, then the lover and the beloved can share a beautiful interchange of love. If through order and philosophy they are able to master themselves, the love in their souls will continue to awaken, their wings will grow, and they will be prepared for their heavenly flight. If not, and they give into sensual indulgence; then they must continue their earthly sojourns. When they do attain their heavenly pilgrimage, the plumage in their wings will match because of their love for each other.188 Through this imaginative rendering, Socrates encouraged his listeners to pursue the heavenly way.

In the Republic Socrates described the tripartite nature of the soul as the appetites which can lead to moneymaking, the aggressive which can make one ambitious, and the learning or reasoning which leads to the love of wisdom. The philosophical is the most capable of ruling. The symbolic image of these is the combination of a many-headed beast, a lion, and a person. The respective virtues of each are self-control, courage, and wisdom. When wisdom, which is the most divine quality, is governing, then the energies are successfully employed, and the soul is in harmony.189 Socrates spoke to the intellect of his listeners and said in effect, "Take charge of your life!"

As Socrates described the rewards of justice and virtue, he noted that even the most evil and vicious person cannot destroy one's own soul. Therefore since the disease of the soul, which is vice, does not destroy it, then the soul must be immortal. Also if the souls died off, where would the new souls come from? To see the soul in its purity, we must not look at it when still marred by the appearance of the body, but contemplate the soul with the eye of reason. If we do, we will find that the love of wisdom and virtue are intimations of its divine and eternal quality.190

Finally in the tale of Er, Socrates recounted how the soul leaves the body at death and travels in the other worlds between lives, how it chooses its own life destiny before it returns to earth, and why philosophy is such a valuable guide not only in this world, but also in the next.191 The soul as our eternal beingness is always with us; therefore consider how important it is that we take care of ourselves!

The classic text on the immortality of the soul is Plato's Phaedo which describes the last hours of Socrates' life on earth. While awaiting the time of his execution, Socrates made the somewhat surprising and humorous statement that the philosopher seeks death. They laughed, because many people might nod in agreement at this description of the philosopher. However, there is a secret doctrine against suicide as if man were a prisoner who had no right to open the door and run away. Socrates explained that this mystery is because the gods are our guardians, and we humans are a possession of theirs. We must wait until the gods call us. Socrates was not at all upset by death, because he believed he was going to the gods who are wise and good. The reason why even in life the philosopher is always dying is because death is the release of the soul from the body, and the philosopher is continually striving to free the soul from the desires, pleasures, and pains of the body. The philosopher is looking for the truth, and because the senses are imperfect guides, one turns one's attention to the ideals and the intelligence of the soul. The soul perceives best directly within itself. When God releases us from the "foolishness of the body, we shall be pure and know ourselves all that is pure." Ultimate purification then is the final release from the body at death. Thus the philosopher practices dying and rejoices at the ultimate liberation.192

Socrates obviously had no fear of death, but his friends still had many doubts. Therefore he took this time to reason with them about the immortality of the soul. Socrates began with the ancient doctrine of reincarnation to show that souls exist before birth and after death. Opposites are generated out of their opposites, and therefore the living come from the dead, and the dead come from the living, just like with sleeping and waking. Again the complete cycle is needed if all souls are not to end up dead. The theory of recollection that learning is the awakening of awareness known before birth implies also that the soul has a previous existence.193

To show that the soul continues to exist after death, Socrates combined the theory of opposites with the understanding of the absolute essences which transcend the physical. The soul exemplifies the principles of the invisible, unchanging, ruling, ordering. All of the qualities of the soul are better and longer lasting than the characteristics of the body. The soul which is kept pure through philosophy will more likely go to the gods, which it resembles, than the soul which has been dragged down through the visible world by attachments to bodily things. Socrates expressed confidence that the soul which is kept clear of the pleasures and pains of the body will not be scattered to the winds at death, but Simmias and Cebes still were not sure.194

Socrates mentioned that the swans are prophetic and sing in anticipation of their deaths, not from sorrow but for joy. The theory that the soul is like a harmony is proven fallacious by the theory of recollection as the harmony does not precede its elements, nor does it have knowledge, nor is it a ruling principle; a harmony admits of degrees of concord and dissonance, but the soul has no degrees as to its being. Finally Socrates explained how the absolute essences cannot admit their opposite. Because the soul is the essence of life, there is no way it could become death. Therefore, the soul is immortal. It is generally recognized that God and the essential form of life and the immortal will never perish. Thus when death attacks a person, the body may die; but the immortal soul retires at the approach of death and is preserved safe and sound, and it truly exists in another world.195

Having demonstrated the logical proof, Socrates moved right into a description of the other world, where the souls live after they have departed from the physical realm. These higher worlds are lighter, brighter, more beautiful and diverse. Socrates gave a detailed description of various rivers, or currents of energy. Although he did not claim that this is a precise picture, he gave his listeners enough information so that they could conceive of the nature and vastness of the other worlds.196 Socrates allayed many of their fears and shared extensive knowledge with his friends.

As we shall explore more fully in the next chapter, Socrates lived and died in harmony with his teachings. He calmly and peacefully took the poison which released him from his physical body.
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 117 发表于: 2009-03-15
SOCRATES
Theory-Practice Correlation

By Sanderson Beck

Now that we have examined the teachings of Socrates, it may be worthwhile to glance back over his life to see how well he practiced what he preached. According to Xenophon and Plato there was a high correlation in terms of Socrates living up to his own ideas.

In Plato's Laches the general of that name declares that he loves and hates discussions depending on whether the speaker who is discoursing on virtue and wisdom has deeds to match or not. He examines how well the words and actions harmonize with each other. When they are in harmony, he rejoices; but when the man is of an opposite character, he is pained and hates the discussion. Laches then says, "Now of Socrates' word I have no experience, but before, as it seems, I have tested his deeds; there I found him worthy of freely speaking all the beautiful words."1 In this case Laches has personally seen Socrates' bravery on the battlefield, but he is as yet unfamiliar with his skill in conversation. As far as this general is concerned, his demonstrated courageous character gives him license to speak whatever he wishes.

Xenophon records in his Symposium that when Socrates recommended that every husband ought to teach his wife whatever he would like her to know, Antisthenes challenges him by asking, "If that is so, Socrates, how is it that you don't practice what you preach by yourself educating Xanthippe, but live with a wife who is the hardest to get along with of all the women there are---or, I think, that ever were or will be?" Socrates explains:

Because I observe that men who wish to become expert horsemen do not get the most docile horses but rather those that are high-spirited, believing that if they can manage this kind, they will easily handle any other. And I, wishing to deal with and associate with people, have acquired the same, well assured that if I can endure her, I will easily be able to relate with all the rest of mankind.2

The rest of the company confirmed the validity of this remark. Socrates did in fact have more trouble with Xanthippe than with anyone else, and his close relationship with her did give him the opportunity to learn how to get along with even a shrew like her.

After relating Socrates' ideas on self-control, Xenophon makes the following observation:

His own self-control was shown yet more clearly by his deeds than by his words. For he kept in control not only the pleasures of the body, but those too that money brings, in the belief that he who takes money from any casual giver puts himself under a master and endures the basest form of slavery.3

Socrates was well-known for his detachment from material things.

In defending Socrates against his accusers who felt he had been corrupting the youth, Xenophon gives more details. Not only did he control his own desires and appetites stricter than anyone, but he could endure any cold or heat and was resolute in labor; his needs were so well trained in moderation that he was content with very little. "This being his character, how could he have led others into impiety, crime, gluttony, lust, or laziness? In fact he helped many get over these by urging them toward goodness and giving them confidence that self-discipline would make them gentlemen."4 He never professed to teach these things, but by manifesting them he gave his disciples hope that they could attain them also. He never neglected the body, and criticized such neglect in others, such as over-eating followed by over-exertion. He recommended as much physical exercise as is pleasing to the soul, for this habit brings good health and does not hamper care of the soul. He disliked foppery and pretentiousness in the fashion of clothes or in behavior, nor did he encourage the love of money among his companions. Although he assisted them, he would not take money even though they desired to give it. This policy he kept in order to assure his own liberty, not selling himself into bondage to anyone. He was surprised that anyone could take money for the spreading of virtue; for him the greatest reward was the gain of a good friend. Certainly anyone who became a gentleman could not fail to feel deep gratitude for such a great benefit. Socrates made no promises to anyone, but he was confident that his companions who adopted these principles of conduct would be life-long good friends to him and to each other.5

Probably Socrates was condemned by many, because he was critical of many of the established practices of the time. He argued that it was foolish to choose public officials by lottery when every other profession depends on knowledge and skill, and mistakes in the minor crafts are less disastrous than the mistakes in statecraft. Some people felt that he led the young to despise the constitution of the city and made them violent. Xenophon reasons in his defense that the cultivation of wisdom and the use of persuasion by words are designed to replace force by safe and friendly means of change. Actually it is power without wisdom that leads to violence; for violence requires physical supporters, while wisdom only needs confidence in its ability to persuade.6 As far as we know, Socrates never attempted to organize his own political force, but rather only acted as an individual counselor in private life. What his students may have done in politics we will examine in the next chapter.

Xenophon concludes his defense of Socrates against the charges of corrupting the youth and rejecting the gods by declaring that he was more deserving of honor on these counts rather than death. He never caused anything bad to happen to the state nor was any man in private life harmed by him. "No man was more conspicuous for his devotion to the service of the gods," and he was so far from corrupting the youth that "if any among his companions had evil desires, he openly tried to reform them and exhorted them to desire the fairest and noblest virtue, by which people prosper in public life and in their homes."7 Perhaps there is some cosmic irony of history here, as with Jesus, that the man who stands out as doing the most for people, receives the most persecution.

Socrates often spoke about justice, so it is fitting that we look at the actions in his life which exemplified justice. Xenophon summarizes many of them.

Again, concerning justice he did not hide his knowledge, but demonstrated it by his actions. All his private conduct was lawful and helpful; to public authority he was so scrupulously obedient in all that the laws required, both in civil life and in military service, that he was a model of good discipline to all. When chairman in the Assembly he would not permit the people to record an illegal vote, but upholding the laws, resisted a popular impulse that might have overcome any but himself. And when the Thirty laid a command on him that was illegal, he refused to obey. Thus he disregarded their repeated injunction not to talk with young men; when they commanded him and certain other citizens to arrest a man on a capital charge, he alone refused, because the order given him was illegal. Also when he was tried on the charge brought by Meletus, even though it is the custom for defendants to ask for favor with the jury and to indulge in flattery and illegal appeals, and many by such means have been known to gain a verdict of acquittal, he completely rejected the familiar trickery of the courts; though he might easily have gotten a favorable verdict by even a moderate indulgence in such stratagems, he chose to die through his loyalty to the laws rather than to live through violating them.8

As we have seen earlier, these courageous deeds in accordance with his beliefs were also described in various works by Plato.

Socrates often made reference to his own actions in discussing a topic, such as the time when Hippias asked him about justice, complaining that Socrates never stated his own ideas. Socrates replied, "I declare them by deeds, anyhow, if not by my words. Don't you think that deeds are better evidence than words?" Hippias agrees, pointing out that many talk about justice and do what is unjust, but no one who acts justly can be unjust. So Socrates asks him, "Then have you ever seen me dealing in perjury or calumny, or stirring up strife between friends or in the city, or doing anything else unjust?"9 Hippias has not. Here again Socrates shows his concern that his actions match his theories.

Xenophon tells how Hermogenes tried to get Socrates to prepare a speech for his defense in court against Meletus; he responded, "Don't you think I have been preparing for it all my life? .. in being constantly occupied in the consideration of right and wrong, and in doing what was right and avoiding what was wrong."10 When Hermogenes persists, Socrates closes the matter by saying that his deity prevented him from preparing a speech ahead.11 Socrates had no need to worry at this particular point; since his entire life was devoted to what was best, this must be a good thing that is happening.

In Plato's Gorgias Socrates declares that doing what is good and just is more important than merely trying to extend one's life-span a little longer. "But O blessed one, don't you see that the noble and the good are something different from saving and being saved? For may not he who is truly courageous not love life so much in terms of a certain amount of time, but surrendering all this to God and believing what the women say that no one escapes destiny, should not he proceed to consider the best way to live out the time of his life?"12 Besides, for the person who is aware that his soul is immortal, it is only a question of where and how well one lives.

Later in the Gorgias Socrates demonstrates his courage in criticizing the state in an effort to improve it even though he is arousing enmity and endangering his own person. Rather he does what he does for the sake of justice, as the physician whose medicine may be painful for a while although it leads to health. Even though his own life might be in danger, Socrates could not lower himself to flatter the state unjustly.13 Socrates did in fact end up making the ultimate sacrifice.

In the Crito we have seen how Socrates demonstrated logically and in actuality that it is better to follow the just laws of the state than to run away and set a bad example for other law-breakers.14

After discussing the immortality of the soul in the Phaedo Socrates personifies the certainty of his knowledge by his calmness as the execution proceeds. When Crito asks him how shall they bury him, Socrates reminds his friend that he is leaving soon and not to confuse his dead body with who Socrates really is.15 Socrates is friendly and cooperative with the jailer who instructs him to drink the poison. Even though his friends request it, Socrates refuses to delay his death beyond the designated time, for he would gain nothing by it. He remained calm and confident to the very end. The narration concludes that of all the men of that time, Socrates was "wisest, most just, and best."16 His equipoise in such circumstance could not help but give confidence to the witnesses present.

Let us conclude this chapter with Xenophon's final summary from his recollections of Socrates.

All who knew what manner of man Socrates was and who pursue virtue continue to this day to miss him beyond all others, as the chief of helpers in the quest of virtue. For myself, I have described him as he was: so pious that he did nothing without counsel from the gods; so just that he did no injury, however small, to any man, but conferred the greatest benefits on all who dealt with him; so self-controlled that he never chose the more pleasant rather than the better course; so wise that he was unerring in his judgment of the better and the worse, and needed no counselor, but relied on himself for his knowledge of them; no less masterly in putting others to the test, and convincing them of error and exhorting them to follow virtue and goodness. He seemed to be all that an excellent and happy man must be.17
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 118 发表于: 2009-03-15
Influence of Socrates
by Sanderson Beck
This chapter has been published in the book CONFUCIUS AND SOCRATES Teaching Wisdom. For ordering information, please click here.

The chief complaints against Socrates were not direct criticisms of his own actions, but rather that he was a corrupting influence on others, especially the young and in regard to religious beliefs. Therefore it is of special importance that we examine the effect he had on those around him.

In Plato's Defense of Socrates, Socrates admitted that many people delighted in listening to his conversations because it was amusing to see the pretenders of wisdom cross-examined. He took the time during his trial to ask if any of those present, who had listened to him, or their fathers or other relatives, would like to come up and testify that any of them were corrupted by him. Looking around the courtroom, he named Crito and his son Critobulus; Lysanias the father of Aeschines; Antiphon, father of Epigenes; Nicostratus. brother of the late Theodotus; Paralus, brother of Theages; Adeimantus and his brother Plato; Aeantodorus and his brother Apollodorus; and there were others. Socrates requested Meletus to use these men or any others as witnesses against him; when he did not, Socrates concluded that it was because he was speaking the truth, while Meletus lied.1 Of all these people who heard Socrates regularly, not one was willing to testify against him.

Earlier in the same speech, Socrates described how some of the young men picked up his style of conversation and angered others who blamed Socrates for corrupting them.

In addition to these things, the youth accompanying me,
who have much leisure, sons of the wealthiest,
delight in hearing people examined,
and they often imitate me, and proceed to examine others;
and then, I think, they find a great many people
who think they know something, but know little or nothing.

So then those examined by them become angry at me,
instead of themselves, and they say,
"This is that damned Socrates who corrupts the youth."2

This explains how the disagreeable experience of those who did not like being refuted by Socrates was multiplied when these others took it up. Also it is likely that they might have lacked some of Socrates' sensitivity in avoiding personal contention while focusing on the ideas.

We get an idea of how much Socrates meant to his close associates in the Phaedo. There Phaedo wrote that at the end they were "believing as though deprived of a father we would spend life thereafter as orphans"3 When Socrates finally drank the poison, those present could not help but weep and cried out until Socrates himself rebuked them and calmed them down.4 Since we are going to trace briefly what happened to his disciples, it is interesting to note who was present as recorded by Plato. Plato himself was mentioned as being ill by the narrator Phaedo, who was there. The native Athenians present were Apollodorus, Critobulus and his father Crito, Hermogenes, Epigenes, Aeschines, and Antisthenes. Ctesippus the Paeanian was also there along with Menexenus and some other Athenians. From Thebes there was Simmias and Cebes, and from Megara Euclides and Terpsion. Aristippus and Cleombrotus were asked about, but they were in Aegina at the time.5

Xenophon mentioned several names of men who associated with Socrates, not so they could make great speeches in the courts or assembly, but so that they might become gentlemen (beautiful and good) and be useful at home to their relatives and friends and in the city to the citizens. He named Crito, Chaerophon, Chaerecrates, Hermogenes, Simmias, Cebes, Phaedonias, and indicated there were others. These men, according to Xenophon, never did any evil nor were they censured at all during their whole lives.6 At least these men were probably helped by Socrates.

Xenophon wrote, however, that although Socrates never collected a fee for the benefits he gave, some who received these things from him did go out and charge a large price and would not speak to those who did not pay.7 Apparently Socrates placed no restrictions on what the disciples could do on their own.

Much of the information on the Socratic philosophers was gathered together by Diogenes Laertius in his Lives of Eminent Philosophers. He recorded that the public attitude changed after Socrates' death: Meletus was put to death; Anytus was expelled from Heraclea; and a bronze statue honoring Socrates was placed in the hall of processions.8

The various successors of Socrates were called Socratics, and Diogenes Laertius held the chief ones to be Plato, Xenophon, and Antisthenes, while he considered Aeschines, Phaedo, Euclides, and Aristippus the most distinguished on the traditional list of ten.9 Let us examine these men and the schools they founded.

Diogenes Laertius assumed, partly because they wrote similar dialogs in competition with each other, that Plato and Xenophon were not on good terms with each other.10 In all their works Plato never mentioned Xenophon, and Xenophon only once referred to Plato in relation to his brother Glaucon, who was portrayed as a fool.

Diogenes related an incident where Antisthenes was going to give a public reading and invited Plato. Plato asked the topic; when Antisthenes said it was on the impossibility of contradiction, Plato wondered how he could possibly write on the subject, showing the argument refuted itself. Consequently Antisthenes wrote a dialog against Plato, and they remained antagonistic to each other.11
According to this same source, Plato did not get along well with Aristippus either. He was jealous of Aeschines because of his reputation with Dionysius in his court, because Plato despised his poverty, and because Aristippus supported him. According to Idomeneus it was actually Aeschines who debated with Socrates in prison, but Plato changed it to Crito because of his dislike of Aeschines.12 Apparently the friendship of Socrates' circle was diminished when the master left.

Aristotle recorded a criticism of Plato by Aristippus because he strayed away from the Socratic approach. "Aristippus replied to Plato when he spoke somewhat too dogmatically, as Aristippus thought, 'Well, anyhow, our friend,' meaning Socrates, 'never spoke like that.'"13 However, according to Cicero the method used in Plato's Academy was to draw one forth toward truth without asserting authority, leaving the inquirer free to choose.14 Certainly the school did become a prominent institution in Athens, and Aristotle studied there for twenty years.

Diogenes Laertius in his life of Plato wrote that he first was interested in poetry and tragedy. One day Socrates had a dream about a cygnet on his knees which suddenly put forth plumage and flew away singing sweetly. The next day when Plato was introduced to him, he recognized him as the swan in his dream. After hearing Socrates at about age twenty, he burned his poetry and became a student of philosophy. Diogenes also recounted his early travels.

When Socrates was gone,
he attached himself to Cratylus the Heraclitean,
and to Hermogenes who professed the philosophy of Parmenides.
Then at the age of twenty-eight according to Hermodorus,
he withdrew to Megara to Euclides,
with certain other disciples of Socrates.
Next he proceeded to Cyrene
on a visit to Theodorus the mathematician,
from there to Italy to see the Pythagorean
philosophers Philolaus and Eurytus,
and then to Egypt to see those
who interpreted the will of the gods.15

Obviously Plato had opportunities to learn many other philosophical ideas in addition to what he had learned from Socrates.

Diogenes felt that Plato dealt with many "themes which Socrates disowned, although he puts everything into the mouth of Socrates."16 However, he did not give any specific examples. He related also that when Socrates heard Plato read the Lysis, he exclaimed, "By Heracles, so many lies this young man is telling about me!"17 Thus it would have been foolish to rely upon Plato for all our knowledge about Socrates.

What about Xenophon? According to Diogenes Laertius, he first encountered Socrates in a narrow passage. Socrates barred his way with a stick and asked him where every kind of food was sold. Then he asked, "Where do people become good and honorable?" Xenophon was in doubt about this. "Then follow me," said Socrates, "and learn." From that time on Xenophon was a student of Socrates. Diogenes wrote that he was the first to take notes of the conversations of Socrates and also to give them out to the world as he did in his Memoirs of Socrates.18 Diogenes concluded that Xenophon "made Socrates his exact model."19 Xenophon, of course, had other interests besides philosophy, such as fighting in foreign wars, estate management, and writing histories, but he did also leave us some valuable recollections of a Socrates, probably less tampered with than the one of Plato's works.

Before we examine the other Socratic schools, let us observe some of the influences on men during Socrates' life-time. Crito was the same age as Socrates and perhaps his closest friend. According to Diogenes, Crito "was most affectionate in his disposition toward Socrates, and took such good care of him that none of his needs were left unsupplied." He also credited Crito with writing seventeen dialogs.20

Menexenus was portrayed in a dialog by Plato as ready to take Socrates' advice as to whether he should go into government of not.21 Apollodorus in narrating Plato's Symposium declared that it had been "almost three years that I have been associating with Socrates and making it my daily business to know whatever he says or does." Apollodorus confessed that before that time he was running around thinking he did things and was the wretchedest man alive.22 Apollodorus got his account of the dinner and speeches from Aristodemus who was "one of the main lovers of Socrates at that time," and he also confirmed the details of the story with Socrates himself.23 These men were devoted to Socrates, but there were others who dabbled in his conversations and then pursued their own ambitions.

Alcibiades is the most famous example of this, who caused a blight on Socrates' reputation. In the Alcibiades I we see Socrates attempting to ward off the dangers of the young man's ambition to rule by showing him his desperate need for education and self-knowledge. Socrates expressed his fear that Alcibiades might be ruined by the Athenian people if he was swayed by the masses unwisely.24 Socrates warned him that ignorance in the ambitious and powerful was the most dangerous, because their mistakes could be costly and disastrous for many people. Ignorance is slavery, and virtue, not power, leads to happiness. Socrates concluded his counseling that he was very much concerned that the power of the state might overcome them.25

In Plato's Symposium we see Alcibiades several years later. Alcibiades showed up drunk wearing a crown which he first placed on Agathon, whose tragedy had just won a victory, but then he took ribbons and crowned Socrates the conqueror of mankind in conversation. Socrates jokingly asked Agathon to protect him from Alcibiades, because he feared his passion and jealousy.26 In Plato's account Alcibiades confessed that he became spellbound when he listened to Socrates. When he left the presence of Socrates his love of popularity overcame him. Even though Socrates made him ashamed of this life, he continued it, sometimes wishing that Socrates were dead.27 Thus was portrayed Alcibiades' ambivalence and confusion concerning Socrates and his political affairs.

Alcibiades stirred up the Athenians to fight in Sicily and got himself elected general. Socrates warned against the expedition because of the intervention of his divine sign. After the armies were gathered, Alcibiades was accused of profaning the sacred mysteries of Demeter and Persephone at a drunken party. This was a capital crime, but the eagerness for the war in Sicily enabled Alcibiades to get a postponement of his trial. When the Sicilian expedition proved disastrous, Alcibiades avoided returning to Athens by going to live in Sparta, the arch-enemy of Athens at that time.28 Thus he was branded a traitor, and that he had spent some time with Socrates was suspicious to many people.

Xenophon explained that Alcibiades only came to Socrates so that he could learn how to be successful in politics. As soon as he had gained enough skill in argument to outwit the other politicians, he left Socrates. To demonstrate this he recorded a conversation between Alcibiades and Pericles in which Alcibiades used a Socratic refutation to show the famous statesman that "laws" made by a minority by force and not persuasion were not really laws; even if the majority of the assembly enacted something on property owners without persuasion, it was not law, but force.29 Thus his limited education was turned into a kind of political weapon for persuasion.

Critias was another one who studied with Socrates and then went into politics as part of the oligarchy of Thirty; Alcibiades' extravagances were under the democracy. According to Xenophon both of these men remained prudent as long as they were in the company of Socrates; but when they left him, their ambition got the better of them.30 For Xenophon good character came from continuous training of the soul. When they went their separate ways, they neglected their training, which had strengthened their ability to conquer their passions. Critias went to Thessaly, where he fell in with lawless men, and Alcibiades on account of his good-looks was tempted by the ladies and the general public.31 We have seen already how Critias resented Socrates' criticism of his lust toward Euthydemus and how he attempted to silence Socrates when he ruled with the Thirty.32 It must be granted that Socrates did not have perfect success with every person who came to him, but neither was he necessarily responsible for all their actions after they left him.

Aeschines, however, remained loyal to Socrates, who said of him, "Only the sausage-maker's son knows how to honor me."33 Diogenes Laertius also informed us that the seven Socratic dialogs which he wrote were said by some to have been obtained from Xanthippe or from Antisthenes. When he was reading one at Megara, Aristippus cried out, "Where did you get that, thief?" He was introduced to the court of Dionysius in Sicily by Aristippus, presented dialogs and received gifts there. It was said that Plato became angry at him for siding with Aristippus.34 A couple of fragments from his dialogs called Alcibiades and Aspasia were presented in earlier chapters, and according to Panaetius the definitely genuine Socratic dialogs were the ones by Plato, Xenophon, Antisthenes, and Aeschines.35

In Xenophon's Symposium Antisthenes asserted that his greatest pride was his wealth. He referred to spiritual wealth as being of more value than real estate or possessions or money. He did not suffer from cold or lack of company; all his needs and desires were met as he drew forth from his soul. He claimed he got this wealth from Socrates and shared it with others. Best of all was his leisure so that he could spend the entire day in the company of Socrates.36 Later on after Socrates had described himself as a procurer, he called Antisthenes a good go-between because he helped Callias to receive lessons from Prodicus on philosophy, from Hippias on a memory system, and others he had brought together for their mutual advantage. He might make an excellent diplomat between cities or arranger of private marriages.37 This was high praise from Socrates.

According to Diogenes Laertius, Antisthenes first studied rhetoric with Gorgias and then later became devoted to Socrates. He lived in the Peiraeus and would walk the five miles to Athens every day to listen to Socrates. From him he picked up his self-disciplined style of life, emulating his detachment from feelings. He advised his own disciples to study with Socrates and originated the Cynic way of life.38 He was critical of Plato's pride; but when Plato was said to have abused him, he remarked, "It is kingly to do good and to hear bad things."39 When some youths, who had heard of the fame of Socrates, came to Athens, he led them to Anytus, whom he ironically called wiser than Socrates; the result was that Anytus was driven out of the city.40 Antisthenes held that virtue was sufficient to insure happiness, but it required the strength of a Socrates.41 His school was said to originate the most courageous section of Stoicism, and Xenophon called him "the most agreeable of men in conversation and the most self-controlled in everything else." His writings went into ten volumes on a wide range of subjects.42 Thus Antisthenes probably represented one of Socrates' finest students who was quite successful in continuing his work.

Aristippus was the first of the Socratics to charge fees. He sent the money to Socrates, who he refused to take it because of his divine sign.43 After a lawyer won a case for him, he asked Aristippus what good Socrates had done him. He replied, "This: that what you said of me in your speech was true."44 Apparently Aristippus was more concerned with his conduct in life than in the ability to make a good speech. When asked how Socrates died, he replied, "As I would pray to die myself."45 Although he was not present at Socrates' death, he did have great respect for his teacher. He said he went to Socrates for wisdom and education and to Dionysius for money and recreation.46 After he made some money by teaching, Socrates asked him, "Where did you get so much?" to which he replied, "Where you got so little."47

Aristippus founded a school in Cyrene, and they were known as the Cyrenaics. They held that life consisted of pleasure and pain, and that happiness is the sum total of all particular pleasures.48 Perhaps it is an indication of how undogmatic Socrates was, that Antisthenes and Aristippus could start schools so radically different in their philosophies.

Phaedo was said to have written some dialogs, but many of them are doubtful as to their authenticity. He developed a school in Elis.49

Euclides also wrote dialogs and had a school in Megara, where his followers were called Megarians, Eristics, and the Dialecticians. He followed Parmenides and declared that everything is good. Hermodorus stated that Plato and other philosophers visited him after Socrates' death because they were alarmed at the cruelty of the tyrants.50

Diogenes Laertius also included a life of Simon, who was a cobbler in Athens. When Socrates would converse in his workshop, he used to make notes, and he was the first, according to some, to present Socratic dialogs.51

Glaucon, Simmias, and Cebes were also mentioned as having written dialogs, though there were also a great many spurious dialogs.52

Thus we can see that many men were so well educated by Socrates that they were successful in developing their own schools. Philosophy had not only become a subject of study, but for many it was now the most important pursuit in life. The Cynics and Cyrenaics were influential for many generations and for several hundred years as they were taken over by Stoicism and Epicureanism. Plato's Academy lasted several centuries, and his philosophy has been a dominant force in the western consciousness even to today. The Socratic works by Xenophon have also been influential across the centuries, and they especially influenced Benjamin Franklin. The Socratic method is probably the most famous and most often imitated pedagogical technique as it has been used by countless teachers and private philosophers. Now that Socrates the educator has been presented, we can summarize and analyze his teaching as we compare it to that of Confucius.
级别: 管理员
只看该作者 119 发表于: 2009-03-15
Confucius and Socrates Compared
by Sanderson Beck
Summary
Life and Deeds
Manner and Attitudes
Style and Methods
Content and Topics
Theory-Practice Correlation
Influence on Followers
Analysis and Synthesis
Recommendations
Bibliography
This chapter has been published in the book CONFUCIUS AND SOCRATES Teaching Wisdom. For ordering information, please click here.

Summary
Having examined the details of the lives and educational work of Confucius and Socrates, let us now summarize the main points of each chapter and examine the similarities and differences between them.

Life and Deeds
Both Confucius and Socrates lived in cultures where hereditary privilege was the main factor in social status. Neither of them was extremely high-born, but they certainly were not peasants either. Confucius as one of the many lower aristocrats was just high enough where he would be considered as a possible official in the government, but not high enough so that he was automatically given a position. Due to his economic circumstances he spent some time working with his hands and in business. Socrates was a citizen, but neither was he related to a ruling family. He probably worked as a stone-mason; he fought in battle not as an officer, but as a citizen soldier. Both apparently received an education as they became very familiar with the literature and music of their cultures. It is doubtful they could have become the educators they did, if they had not been born in circumstances where they could be educated. Neither one seemed to have an especially significant teacher, but they both related to an ideal pattern, sometimes exemplified by the ancients. Their admiration for the classical writings of their cultures and their extensive knowledge of them indicates deep and prolonged study. Confucius spent some time playing music, and Socrates set some fables to music while in prison due to guidance from a dream.

Their not having been in the highest class probably was a major factor in preventing an active and powerful political life. Socrates intentionally stayed out of politics due to his spiritual guidance, but did become an advisor and teacher to some who did engage in political leadership. Similarly Confucius although he tried to become politically effective, served mainly as an advisor and educator of politicians. However, his efforts in this area did make Confucius more involved in government than Socrates' incidental services as a citizen.

Both men were attracted to the human culture of city life, although Confucius did travel around, while Socrates did not. They both were most interested in relating with people. We know very little about the younger years of either of them, but by middle age they each had attracted a group of students around them. Socrates claims he never accepted money; but either he must have accepted minimal gifts to live on or he had an independent income, because he spent all his days in conversation. Confucius accepted gifts and had a group of regular students, but there is no indication that he used his teaching to become wealthy. In fact both of them were open to discussing ideas with any one who bothered to come to them. Both of them appeared to be inexhaustible in their efforts to pursue wisdom; there is no record of anyone outlasting them in this persistence.

Perhaps the key event in both their lives was when they realized their divine mission. Confucius said he was fifty when he knew the will of Heaven. Socrates does not say when the Delphic oracle made its famous pronouncement which stimulated his quest for a wise man, but it is likely that it was in his forties. In both cases, most of what we know about these two men occurred after this turning point in their lives. This sense of their mission and divine-appointed destiny must have strengthened their purpose considerably. Because of this relationship with the divine or a higher power, neither of them seemed to have any fear of death or anything else. Neither Confucius nor Socrates would do something they considered to be unjust even if they were being intimidated by threats. Their actions were strictly regulated by their rational or intuitive evaluation of what was right. Confucius died a natural death at seventy-two, while Socrates was martyred at seventy, but both accepted death calmly.

Manner and Attitudes
Confucius was polite, cordial, and deferential. His humility was sincere, and most people seemed to get along with him rather easily. He was friendly and had a good sense of humor. Socrates also was friendly and perhaps even more humorous. However, his attitude of modesty was perceived as being ironic by most people who probably felt the power of his ego even though he tried to be self-effacing. Confucius made courtesy a fine art in his respect for human beings, whereas Socrates was only able to temper his straightforwardness by means of the irony. Neither one claimed to be wise.

Although Confucius was temperate and self-disciplined, Socrates took these qualities farther into a more ascetic life-style. However, they both loved relating with people and delighted in company. They both were very open to all types of people and expressed a deep concern for individuals and for humanity.

It would be hard to find anyone who loved to learn more than Confucius and Socrates. They turned every situation in which they found themselves into an exploration of some topic. Their perseverance in pursing wisdom and education seemed continual and enduring. They were always open to questions and examined any idea which would arise; they did not allow any belief which they may have had to dogmatically block them from considering another idea. Along with this openness, they were also scrupulously honest in presenting their own ideas. They certainly were not afraid of speaking their criticisms to others.

Although they both were cheerful and friendly, they were remarkably unemotional. Neither one of them allowed himself to become a victim of fear or anger or jealousy or resentment. Somehow, perhaps due to their philosophic minds, they were able to handle criticism, threats, mockery, and abuse with such understanding that they were not perturbed by it at all. Their attitudes remained remarkably positive. Even though they were often judged to be failures by the world, neither one of them ever was known to become depressed or unhappy. There always seemed to be a joy and enthusiasm with Confucius and an even-temperedness with Socrates. Even when criticizing what they did not like, their attitudes seemed to remain neutral.

Although they both were humanistic in their concern to help people improve themselves, they both based their purpose on faith in a higher power. This even takes on a mystical quality as they felt that their work was fulfilling the will of Heaven in the case of Confucius, and serving God in the case of Socrates. Their sense of divine mission gave them each an inner strength which was unshakable. They both also believed in various ways of communicating with the divine or higher intelligence. Confucius used the oracle of Changes, and Socrates based his mission on the oracle of Apollo. Both felt they gained useful communication from their dreams, and they were aware of natural portents. Socrates related very closely with the other world and the legendary heroes, while Confucius based his cultural ideals on the ancient pattern and especially the Duke of Zhou. Socrates' guiding spirit was a communication developed to a rather unique level, but they both believed in the power and importance of prayer. The reason why neither one claimed to be wise probably was because they both knew the divine wisdom was far greater than theirs.

Neither one cared much for pretense as each one was offered a better suit of clothes to die in by one of their disciples, but they both politely refused to change their life-style at that point. Neither of them was afraid of death, as they both peacefully accepted it.

Style and Methods
Both Confucius and Socrates taught rather informally and used primarily a conversational method. They both were open to listening to anyone, but often they would advise the person to seek out someone with more expertise in a particular area such as farming or gardening.

Socrates often began with a prayer for divine guidance and occasionally found himself inspired. Confucius was willing to accept anyone who purified himself before he came to him.

Confucius expected his students to make some effort if he was to help them. Socrates usually only required that they answer his questions. Naturally both of them were more enthusiastic when dealing with those who were more intelligent. They both encouraged everyone to learn and work on improving themselves and presented various reasons and arguments to exhort them in this direction.

Both Confucius and Socrates maintained an atmosphere of friendship and even camaraderie. Their cheerfulness, enthusiasm, and humor gave the discussions a positive feeling that was uplifting. They demonstrated not only intellectual subtlety but also sensitivity toward the feelings of others. They both were good listeners.

It was natural that they would individualize their instruction, since rarely if ever did they have a large group. Many of their conversations with a single person were counseling sessions on personal problems or specific goals of the person. Often Confucius and Socrates were not concerned with formulating a universal truth but rather were attempting to help a person find an answer which was suitable to him. Different personalities called for different approaches. Socrates with his method of questioning was particularly successful at drawing out people and revealing to them their particular internal contradictions or weaknesses which needed correction or improvement. Confucius often would merely point it out directly; however, he would usually do it in a way which would stimulate the positive direction. Neither one was afraid to be candid in his criticism.

Confucius would often enlighten his students by his answers to their questions. Occasionally he would stimulate their thinking by asking open-ended questions so they could discuss with each other various individuals' answers. Socrates, on the other hand, rarely asked open-ended questions, and unless requested to do so did not really prefer to have to answer questions put to him. His chief method, of course, was to ask a series of questions in such as way as to thoroughly test the person's knowledge of the subject. In this way he did not have to preach or lecture, but could examine the person's awareness itself. This gave the answerer freedom of choice and enabled him to be active rather than passive in the discussion, although it is not as free and active as open-ended questioning. Yet Socrates could work very specifically on clarifying the person's responses. This philosophical midwifery was designed to assist the person in bringing forth their own understanding and knowledge. If their understanding was not clear and organized in their mind, this process of testing would reveal the errors to them. In the refutation and dialectical methods Socrates surpasses Confucius in his ability to reason. Confucius seemed to rely almost exclusively on his intuition. However, most of his intuitions were so perceptive that they proved to be accurate and workable for many people.

Neither Confucius nor Socrates were poets, but they both used metaphors and analogies as pedagogical tools to make their points more understandable. Confucius would use the imagery of Nature, and he often quoted from the classical poems or referred to legend and history. Confucius and Socrates were similar in that they both used these metaphors and examples primarily to elucidate a moral or ethical point. For them poetry and literature were important as stimulation toward a virtuous life. Socrates often used examples from everyday life to show his listener the simplicity of his meaning in a way he could easily understand. Again Socrates seems to have gone beyond Confucius in the elaborate allegories he told to illustrate higher levels of meaning and experience. He also showed complex relationships by means of analogy and ratios or proportions. They both mentioned incidents from history or legend in order to illustrate a point, often in relation to politics.

Although Confucius was concerned about the correct use of language and he did work on defining certain terms, Socrates took the quest for clear definitions into a more comprehensive examination. Occasionally Confucius would ask someone to clarify his meaning, but usually he was giving his own intuitive understanding of the concepts his students were asking about. Confucius was very concerned that communication be honest and that one's actions match one's words. Confucius was not interested in mere verbal education but actual self-improvement. However, he did recognize the possible misuses of language, and therefore was very concerned that words were used correctly.

Socrates was also wary of sophistical games, and was continually attempting to clarify what a person meant by a certain word. His pursuit of the meaning of abstract ideas has been considered one of his main contributions to philosophy. The purpose of his dialectical method was to come to some agreement on the essential principles of life. Socrates attempted to gain these understandings by asking the appropriate questions. Confucius, after studying and pondering, would present his intuitive understandings in proverbial sayings which his disciples could contemplate upon and use as guides for conduct.

Content and Topics
Confucius and Socrates relied on others to provide the traditional education which involved reading and writing, music, and physical training or sports. Confucius placed emphasis on studying the classical literature, whereas Socrates probably did not need to since the educated were probably expected to know Homer and other poets and myths. Part of Confucius' work may have been to edit the classics and make them available to more people. Socrates knew the poetry and myths of his culture, but used them as references rather than as subjects for their own sake. Confucius, however, loved to study the odes with his students, although, like Socrates, he did emphasize their moral lessons. Socrates found that poetry was more related to inspiration than to wisdom, and according to Plato he was especially concerned about the moral influence of this imitative art. Both of them considered it important to classify the different types of music and their effect.

Although Confucius and Socrates prepared many men for politics which required the ability to speak well, they both were wary of clever talk and the art of rhetoric. Rather their main concern was that their disciples have a good understanding of justice as the single most important factor of political life. Much of their time and energy was spent in the study of right and wrong and what constitutes the good society. They both observed and utilized the analogy between the family and state in describing rulership and human relations. Both stressed the value and importance of ideals and portrayed the ideal state in the midst of various prevailing governments which were far from perfect. They criticized their unjust practices and diagnosed their problems. Socrates seemed to go into more detail in delineating the different types of government.

Confucius taught propriety which is perhaps a more socially-oriented equivalent of temperance and self-control. For Confucius the rules of propriety were the social controls for the proper behavior of a gentleman. They maintained the social graces and guaranteed appropriate refinement in manners and conduct. For Socrates and the Greeks personal behavior was focused more on the individual as his own responsibility of self-discipline and did not extend so strongly into the social milieu. The rules of propriety were designed to bring harmony in relationships, while temperance is concerned with the harmony within the individual. In the negative, the difference might be between shame and guilt. In both cases, desires and pleasures were the things to watch out for, and Confucius and Socrates cautioned their disciples and encouraged them to seek wisdom along with the more refined pleasures.

Religion was serious and important to both Confucius and Socrates. Yet as humanists neither wasted his time discussing the supernatural or speculative if it did not have some practical value. They were more concerned with understanding human beings
and how we can improve ourselves than in attempting to understand the nature of the universe. Although they both recognized and obeyed a transcendental reality, their concern was for man. How could people practice the Way of piety or holiness? They believed that by study and investigation they could discover how to act so as to serve Heaven or the gods. Yet they also were aware that some questions were beyond man's reasoning abilities, and in these cases they recommended consulting the divine through oracles, portents, or other rituals. They realized that there is a higher intelligence than human wisdom.

The main idea of education for both Confucius and Socrates was virtue and self-improvement. Here we begin to find even more of a remarkable similarity in the teachings of these two men. What is the true function or excellence of a man, and how can he develop this quality? Confucius, like Socrates, knew that the human tendency was to love beauty more than virtue, but they both endeavored to show that by becoming more virtuous, everything in a person's life could improve. In fact virtue is the way to happiness, even if few follow it. Socrates believed that it is due to ignorance of what is really good for a person, because everyone does what they believe is good. Confucius likewise took an educational approach to lead people toward the good life. Both men pointed out the errors and suffering caused by various vices, and showed how acting virtuously leads to success.

The specific virtues they discussed are again amazingly similar. A traditional virtue in both cultures was courage, but it was only a necessary part of virtue and had to be tempered to avoid rashness. However, the courage to do the right thing is indispensable to the good life.

The key virtue which could be developed through learning is wisdom. Both particularly emphasized self-knowledge as the most significant. This included knowing what one knows and knowing what one does not know. This higher recognition enables one to use his knowledge correctly and avoid mistakes in the areas of his ignorance. As educators these two men constantly focused the attention of people on themselves so they could turn inward and examine their own character, concepts, goals, methods, attitudes, etc. After having looked at these things with their assistance, Confucius and Socrates would often suggest ways they could improve themselves.

For Confucius and Socrates learning and wisdom were what integrated and related the other virtues and areas of study into a coherent whole. Wisdom gained through learning and investigation or recognized intuitively is the guide for all action along with the good.

For Confucius human-heartedness or goodness is a personal quality innate within each person but rarely realized in its full potential. Goodness is the correct loving relationship between people, and the source of the virtues and all values. For Socrates love is the energy which moves us toward the good which is the divine reality and center of the spiritual world. The proper human relationship is friendship, and the good is the transcendental reality which is the source of the ideals and what should be our guide in every action. Both men lived and taught in a spirit of friendliness and continually focused their energy on the good in each situation. They first worked on improving themselves and then worked to assist others toward a better life.

In addition to setting a personal example they also discussed the ideal person or gentleman and what his characteristics are so that their disciples would have an abstract model to follow. This way they could strive for the ideal in their own way without trying to copy the personalities of their teachers. The gentleman or superior man of Confucius and the gentleman or good and beautiful man of Socrates both had tremendous impact in changing their culture's values from the nobility of birth to the nobility of good character. Above all, the gentleman is ethical and fair to everyone. He is friendly and always maintains a dignified courtesy toward people. He exemplifies the virtues although he may not yet be a divine sage or philosopher king. These higher ideals discussed by Confucius and Socrates could not be found in their societies, but are presented as a goal and future hope for mankind.

In his discussions of the immortality of the soul and its journeys to the other worlds Socrates goes beyond the knowledge we have of Confucius. The transcendental teachings of Chinese culture were brought forward more by the Daoists than by Confucius. Socrates appears to demonstrate more of an ability than Confucius did in uniting the human with the divine.

Theory-Practice Correlation
Although both Confucius and Socrates used the discussion method, they both were very conscientious about acting according to their ideas. This is most noticeable in their concern for justice. Confucius would not serve in a government that was not fair to the people even though he seemed rather ambitious for political position and power. As an ethical teacher he did not allow himself to engage in actions which he believed were not right. Socrates knew intuitively that it would be far too dangerous for him to bring his ethical standards into the realm of politics in his time. He did not choose to throw his life away in attempting immediate political reform. Even in living a private life, he showed integrity and justice in his occasional dealings with the state, and he did end up sacrificing his life for the sake of justice. Both men were able to accept lack of recognition and even ridicule, exemplifying that they did not need others' approval to validate their own wisdom. They demonstrated exceptional equanimity.

Confucius continually emphasized that wisdom consists of both knowledge and action. They could discuss what was wise, but it is the actions of the person which demonstrated whether he is actually wise or not. For Socrates also true knowledge or wisdom or virtue was verified by deeds; the person who does not act correctly does not truly know what is right. Only in this strong sense that knowledge is also right action does Socrates mean that virtue is knowledge.

Influence on Followers
Neither Confucius nor Socrates left any major writings like so many other philosophers have done, but like Buddha and Jesus, they had devoted disciples who passed along their message. The teachings of Confucius became not only the dominant philosophy of China but its major religion as well. Somehow the disciples managed to write down the conversations and keep the different schools and tendencies among the disciples unified.

In Socrates' case, his open and non-dogmatic style and his emphasis on what the other person thought rather than on his own ideas led to several individual disciples going their separate ways. The result was several prominent schools with the most influential being the Platonic philosophy. Although the various schools were called Socratic, Socrates became the stimulator rather than the founder of a great philosophy.

Many of the students of Confucius and Socrates became active in politics and had some degree of success. However, in both cases some of the activities of their former students were not quite as they had hoped they would be. As these examples indicate, their ability to transform their listeners into men of virtue was far from perfect. There is evidence though that many men were able to improve themselves to some degree under the influence of Confucius' and Socrates' education.

Now let us see what our exposure to these two men might be able to do for us.

Analysis and Synthesis
Having described the life and teachings of Confucius and Socrates and summarized their similarities, let us now see if we can analyze and explain this process of pursuing wisdom and the good life through learning so as to account for what they did and what others might be able to do as well.

The goal of the educator is for others to learn. Therefore it may be more useful and simpler to begin by focusing on the learner rather than on the teacher. For the most part the students or listeners of Confucius and Socrates were grown men. Although some were youths, we are primarily concerned here with higher education or adult learning. Thus the problems of children and compulsory education are beyond the limitations of this discussion. The students and followers of Confucius and Socrates freely chose to listen to them; even those who just happened to find themselves encountering these men still had the choice to disregard what they heard. Confucius expected his students to be motivated enough to make effort. However, motivations varied; some sought a higher salary more than they sought wisdom. Socrates also had to contend with ambition as a motivation.

How did they attract the learners' attention toward wisdom and the good life? One way is through personal example or modeling. By diligently seeking wisdom themselves Confucius and Socrates stimulated others who observed them to emulate their quest. However, this does not explain why the learner should follow them, except that he intuits it will be successful or he merely desires to be like this person. Although these are not rational grounds, this probably does occur.

How did they use reasoning? Confucius and Socrates both used conversation, which is still available today and can even be broadcast on radio or television. There are many other methods such as literature, art, drama, group processes, etc. Certainly conversation or dialectic is not the only method, but it is the one we are dealing with here. How does conversation motivate the learner to pursue wisdom? Both Confucius and Socrates encouraged others to search for wisdom and goodness by means of exhortations. The exhortation is designed to communicate to the learner that virtue or wisdom or goodness are worth pursuing. They might demonstrate to an ambitious Alcibiades or Zilu that the proper education is a means whereby they would be able to achieve their goals. Whatever the goal might be, whether to win a lover, end a quarrel, command an army, or become a minister in the government, they would emphasize that virtue, justice, and self-control or propriety were what was needed to attain it in a successful way. By reasoning, or question and answer step by step, or by mentioning the process and its consequences aphoristically, the exhortation is a technique of transmuting values.

What does transmuting values mean? The most abstract or greatest value is the good or goodness. As Socrates believed, everyone does what he thinks or feels or believes to be good; no one intentionally does evil, for such would be a contradiction of human motivation. The pragmatic verification of this is simply that whatever a person consciously does indicates what that person believed was good. Of course, many actions are judged by others or even by the same person later as having been bad in that they might have been better. This difference of opinion implies a difference in what was valued in the situation, and it may or may not imply a greater awareness. For Socrates, knowledge of what is virtuous or truly good is accompanied by the corresponding action, or it is not knowledge at all. Knowledge does not err, and not to do what is good would be an error. Therefore to know what is good and not do it is a contradiction. The implication is that the good life depends on knowledge. If knowledge of the good, which might be called wisdom, is attained, then the actions will be good also.

The educational question then is: How can we learn to know the good? Confucius substantially agrees. His concept jen can mean goodness or humanity of human-heartedness, and coupled with wisdom seems to be the goal of his educational pursuits. For Confucius this is the true essence of what it means to be human in the best way. Although he seems to believe that it is an innate quality, the manifestation of it is rare indeed. In Xenophon, Socrates describes the good as what is useful or helpful in any situation, and in Plato it is an absolute essence which lights the intelligible world, the guide for all action.

Everyone has their opinion of what is good in each situation, but people often choose lesser goods due to their ignorance of a greater good. What techniques can be used to lead people into a greater awareness of what is truly good? One method is through divine inspiration. God or Heaven is usually defined as certainly knowing the good, if not in fact being the good. In the transcendental approach which usually bypasses the reason, the attempt is to align the individual will with the divine will or the order of Heaven. Confucius refers to the sage who follows the Way intuitively. Again this is a rare case, but Confucius himself felt that he had attained the mandate of Heaven. Socrates also in his mission sought to obey the will of God. In the Meno when they are not able to find any rational teachers of virtue, he suggests that people may be virtuous due to divine inspiration. However, for Socrates such inspiration did not imply knowledge but merely right opinion. Socrates held that knowledge or wisdom also includes the ability to defend one's ideas through reasoning. Thus the transcendental method was not sufficient for Socrates. Although inspiration is one approach, it seems that it must be verified either by reasoning or by pragmatic results in order not to confuse it with religious fraud or self-deception.

We turn now to the main focus of both these teachers, and that is self-knowledge. Since it is the people who act, and people who reap the results of their actions, if they could know themselves as active beings, half the problem might be solved. The other half would involve knowledge of others and the world with which we interact. What is the self? Socrates uses the term "soul" (psyche) by which he often comes close to the meaning of consciousness, except that it also includes being. For Socrates the soul has the divine attributes of intelligence and immortality and can live in other worlds beyond the physical body. When in the divine realms the soul has knowledge of the good and other essences, but when it comes into the body it forgets these things until they are reawakened through experience. Such a theory is difficult for many people, because it deals with the transcendental and invisible realities. Although it may seem weird, it does explain the phenomena of consciousness which is active, alive, vitalizing, and most important here, which can learn. Obviously dead bodies do not learn. Confucius also believed in the invisible spirits who had been in the bodies of the ancestors. What does this have to do with self-knowledge? Essentially it means that both these men recognized or believed in man as a spiritual being that transcends the life of the body. Are these doctrines necessary to the pursuit of wisdom and the good life? Maybe not, but they do explain how man's nature is related to the spiritual nature of the divine, why man has the ability to learn, and why wisdom and ethics are important beyond the consequences of a single lifetime. Again these spiritual aspects may not be necessary for someone to become wiser, and there is no way to prove them (or disprove them) except to indicate that they do explain the phenomena.

In regard to social relations Confucius and Socrates discussed the ideal person or gentleman and his qualities. Here we find a more useful intermediary between divine perfection and the various opinions of the learners. Here reason can be used to show how virtuous actions lead to good results. Virtues such as courage and self-control or propriety can be investigated or described as guideline values which may be superior to the desires, ambitions, emotions, and notions of the learners. Confucius would explain to this students how virtuous actions bring success and happiness for everyone. He could back this up and make it clearer by referring to poetry or history or current events. By general discussion various views of people present could be compared to see which were better. This process uses both reasoning and intuition, and requires some thought by the listener.

Socrates also investigated the virtues, but usually did it in such a way as to uncover the opinions of the other person in order to show him their limitations and contradictions. Reasoning is used extensively and intuition could be helpful in calling forth answers. Whereas Confucius tended to present the answer, Socrates usually only stimulated others to think to find the answer themselves. This difference in emphasis may be why the teachings of Confucius became a dogmatic and traditional religion, while Socrates stimulated various schools of philosophy or seekers of wisdom.

In either case the purpose is to transmute the values of the person to a higher level: to show the ambitious, aspiring politician that justice for all is better for everyone including him than personal power without wisdom; to demonstrate that wisdom is more helpful in finding happiness than the gratification of desires and pleasure. Although some pleasures seem better because they are more immediate, in the overall situation there may be a wiser course of action which will result in less pain. In examining one's personal life, self-control of desires becomes a key virtue. In social relationships justice and the principles of propriety are what will work best in the long run for everybody. Thus the wider more universal understanding is shared with the learners by the various methods so they can gain the perspective to see these things in their own lives. If they can recognize the value of the virtue, then they can apply it and improve the quality of their lives.

Let us examine more closely what is meant here by virtue and how it relates to the good, learning, and the specific virtues. We are using virtue here in the broad meaning of its ancient usage rather than in the Christian sense of chastity or of the theological virtues such as faith, hope, and charity. Confucius' word teh translated as virtue could mean spiritual power or moral force, and Socrates' concept of arete meant excellence. In both cases the implication is of the human ability to do or be good, or to function in the best way. Although the definition that virtue is the ability to attain what is good seems to have been refuted by Socrates in the Meno, his argument can be shown to be fallacious. His argument that a man may attain a good thing by unjust means assumes that the man's opinion of what is good is correct, and it neglects to recognize that an unjust action is not good. (See "What Socrates Taught" note 67.) Thus virtue can be understood as what enables one to live the good life. Vice, its opposite, is not good, but is usually defined as evil. Also it is generally recognized that the virtuous person leads a good life. Let us assume these common definitions and see if we can discover the necessary and sufficient conditions of virtue which lead to the good life.

Let us examine wisdom, courage, temperance, justice, and piety (holiness), which were discussed explicitly by Socrates and implicitly by Confucius. Wisdom in relation to virtue was often used broadly to imply that whoever was wise would also be virtuous, because he would know how to be just, temperate, courageous, and pious. Wisdom also includes self-knowledge, for without self-knowledge one makes mistakes, but the wise certainly do not make mistakes. Therefore the wise know themselves, and to become wise it is necessary to learn about ourselves. However, a mere intellectual knowledge of ourselves may not be sufficient to the complete wisdom. If we take wisdom in this larger sense, then we must analyze the parts played by justice, temperance, courage, and piety. If each of these are necessary conditions for virtue, and if they are different, then the lack of any of them will not be sufficient for wisdom or virtue. What are they, and how are they each necessary?

Courage is what enables us to do what we know is right, for the failure to do what we know is right is cowardice, its opposite. Wisdom and courage have a close relationship. Courage is doing what is good, and wisdom is knowing what is good and knowing to do it. Thus courage depends on wisdom as its guide, but it is also a necessary part of wisdom and virtue. Without courage wisdom and virtue would be ineffective and hypocritical. However, wisdom and virtue are effective and do have integrity, because courage is a necessary part of them.

Temperance is controlling one's own desires, appetites, and passions so as to handle oneself in the best way. Whereas courage enable us to act, temperance is the ability to restrain ourselves. Knowledge of our passions and indulgences is helpful but not sufficient for virtue or for complete wisdom. We must also know how to control and discipline negative traits and also actually do it. Thus temperance also has a close relationship with wisdom and virtue, and is a necessary part of them.

Justice simply means what is right or fair, but how is this decided? For Confucius it was the golden rule of not doing to others what you do not wish them to do to you. Justice was to be practiced according to the rules of propriety. For Socrates it is following the laws or covenants of the society and also the divine or universal laws. Both referred to the punishments and recompense for injustice. Justice involves social relations and principles which may have been ordained by God and which are agreed upon by people. However, laws that are not universally agreed upon as being good for the whole society may not be just. Injustice usually involves some injury to another person. Punishment and reward imply that somehow actions are balanced in terms of good and evil. The just person therefore does not harm people, and justice itself maintains the balance even if it means punishment. Although punishment may seem like hurt, Socrates explains that it is better for the soul to receive correction; it is ultimately more harmful for the soul not to receive the needed punishment. Socially justice is essential for the good life and therefore is essential to wisdom and virtue. Again wisdom is necessary in order to know what is right.

Piety or holiness is the virtue of having a good relationship with God or spiritual things. For Confucius it meant the proper worship of the spirits including the ancestors and the proper human relationships. Socrates looked at holiness (in Xenophon) as obeying the laws of God as justice is obeying the laws of man. For those who believe in God or a higher reality, holiness is a necessary part of wisdom and virtue for the good life in this world and the next, because it keeps man in the proper relationship with the divine. It may also bring the inspiration helpful to wisdom and a knowledge of what is good. If the divine laws and principles are good, the person who understands them may have the best guidelines for the good life. For the atheist and agnostic, holiness may not seem to be necessary to wisdom or virtue and the good life on earth at all. A person may still be courageous, temperate, just, and even wise in this world without pursuing piety. However, it might be argued that such a person is following divine law and is pious without knowing it; he is only lacking the understanding of the divine connection. From this viewpoint holiness is helpful and necessary to complete wisdom and to the good life which extends beyond this physical world.

Thus we have analyzed the necessary conditions of wisdom and virtue which lead to the good life. Is there a difference between wisdom and virtue? Virtue is a general term which usually includes wisdom, while wisdom more specifically implies knowledge. Yet we have seen a close relationship between wisdom and the other virtues which enable the one who knows what is good to do it. Courage, temperance, and justice are definitely necessary to virtue, and wisdom is not only necessary to virtue but it is necessary to courage, temperance, and justice. Thus we might say that wisdom is the key to all of virtue. This is especially significant, because wisdom is the virtue closest and most accessible to learning, since it deals with knowledge.

Learning concerns not only knowledge but opinions as well. The purpose of this type of education is somehow to teach or awaken in the student the knowledge of what is good and the awareness that he ought to practice it as well. This process of enlightenment changes opinions to knowledge and what we called transmuting values from selfish and limited notions to universal and beneficial truths.

This is what Confucius and Socrates were attempting to do. Confucius primarily used a positive and intuitive approach as he tried to get his students to see and recognize the value of these truths. Socrates usually employed a negative and reasoning method as he would refute all of their false opinions and stimulate them to think about the truth of these essential concepts with the underlying assumption that the soul would be able to recognize them once the errors they had been holding to were pointed out.

Neither Confucius nor Socrates were completely successful in the process. Therefore it is clear that their methods were not sufficient to attain the good life. They probably are not even necessary, for some may be born and grow up to naturally demonstrate these abilities or virtues. Yet they both had some degree of success as indicated by the lasting influence they had on their respective cultures. It is impossible to measure the subtle improvements in the lives of millions who have been exposed to their teachings.

If we can recognize that wisdom and virtue lead to the good life, and since everyone desires the good life, then whatever methods which are successful in the pursuit of wisdom may be helpful to us. Although many of the techniques and ideas of Socrates and Confucius may seem simple and commonplace, teachers and students of wisdom may not be practicing them as well as we might. There is no reason why the conversational method cannot be applied today with the help of these guidelines either formally or informally. It is to stimulate and encourage this pursuit of wisdom that this comprehensive study of the lives and teachings of Confucius and Socrates has been written.

Recommendations
What have we learned about educating for wisdom? What did Confucius and Socrates do which has not only given them a reputation as two of the wisest men but also as great educators? What principles and techniques stand out which we could apply today?

The first thing that really stands out is their tremendous love of learning and their continual and life-long efforts to improve themselves. If we truly desire to become wiser, and perhaps in addition to assist others in this process, then we must be open to learning as much as we can from everyone with whom we interact. Our purpose in each situation ought to be to learn from the experience. It is obvious that we can only help others to the extent of our own wisdom. Therefore our first goal ought to be to learn to be as wise as we can. This requires desire or love of learning, effort, persistence, endurance, patience, etc.

Also wisdom for Confucius and Socrates meant goodness, correct human relations, friendship, justice, self-control, and propriety. Thus our attitude toward other people and how we treat them is very important. Love of learning in the greater sense is not mere mental exercise but practice in good living, practice in human association, practice in self-discipline, practice in self-examination. We must know ourselves, and to do that we must look at our faults and weaknesses and negative tendencies. Once we begin to see these, then we can work on correcting them. As we observe our own actions and make effort to improve their quality as beneficial, then we refine out many of the unneeded attributes and develop our positive characteristics. As Confucius and Socrates advised, we notice that the company we keep is a significant factor in our personal growth. By associating with other people who are working on improving themselves we can gain more insights not only about ourselves but about people in general. Confucius said that wisdom is to know people, and goodness is to love people. Through loving relationships we can practice and experience being beneficial to each other.

We can also use the guidelines which Confucius and Socrates independently discovered. The foremost guideline in every action is the good which as a spiritual reality can be the focus of our attention. The intuitive perception of what is good in any situation so it can be acted on is the goal of the philosopher and the sage. In the development of human personality the virtues give us valuable reference points for character. Are we disciplining our lower desires and pleasures so that our actions will be more beneficial? Are we acting courageously based upon our higher values? Is this action just and fair to everyone? Is it wise and beneficial? Another key is to focus our attention on the divine or Heavenly Way of doing things; this can give us insight into how we can serve the greater good of all.

Now, assuming that we are practicing these things and making some progress, what can we do to stimulate others in the pursuit of wisdom and the good life? Of course, our personal example will probably speak loudest, but what else? We can be open and loving with people to facilitate communication. We can pursue the quest for wisdom together and inquire into the nature of the good life. We can test and question each other in order to reveal where our knowledge is well-founded and where we are still ignorant or confused. We can study the lessons of history and literature and of current events and how these may apply to our own lives. As we gain more self-knowledge we will probably become more aware of the life of our immediate community and how that can be improved. Eventually we can look at the problems of society as a whole; and if our own personal lives are working well, we can consider what contributions we could offer in whatever area of responsibility we choose. Human life on this earth is not nearly as happy and fulfilling as it could be - individually and collectively. Therefore whatever efforts we make to improve ourselves and society would certainly be worthwhile.

Bibliography
CONFUCIUS
Chan, Wing-tsit A Sourcebook in Chinese Philosophy.
Creel, H. G. Confucius: The Man and the Myth.
Do-Dinh, Pierre Confucius and Chinese Humanism.
Hsu, Cho-yun Ancient China in Transition.
Hughes, E. R. The Great Learning & The Mean-In-Action.
Legge, James Confucius: Confucian Analects, The Great Learning and the Doctrine of the Mean.
Lin Yutang, The Wisdom of Confucius
Mote, Frederick W. Intellectual Foundations of China.
Pound, Ezra Confucius: The Unwobbling Pivot, The Great Digest, The Analects.
Waley, Arthur, The Analects of Confucius.
Ware, James R. The Sayings of Confucius.
Wilhelm, Richard Confucius and Confucianism.
Wilhelm, Richard and Baynes, Cary F. The I Ching or Book of Changes.

SOCRATES
Aristophanes The Clouds tr. Benjamin Bickley Rogers.
Aristotle Metaphysics tr. W. D. Ross.
Aristotle Nicomachaean Ethics tr. W. D. Ross.
Aristotle Politics tr. Benjamin Jowett.
Diogenes Laertius Lives of Eminent Philosophers in two volumes tr. R. D. Hicks.
Field, G. C. Plato and His Contemporaries.
Guthrie, W. K. C. Socrates.
Jaeger, Werner Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture.
Plato, The Collected Dialogues of ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns.
Plato, The Dialogues of tr. Benjamin Jowett.
Plato in twelve volumes Loeb Classical Library.
Plutarch "On the Sign of Socrates" tr. Phillip H. De Lacy and Benedict Einarson.
Strauss, Leo Xenophon's Socrates.
Strauss, Leo Xenophon's Socratic Discourse: An Interpretation of the Oeconomicus.
Taylor, A. E. Socrates: The Man and His Thought.
Vlastos, Gregory (ed.) The Philosophy of Socrates: A Collection of Critical Essays.
Xenophon Memorabilia and Oeconomicus tr. E. C. Marchant; Symposium and Apology tr. O. J. Todd.
Zeller, E. Socrates and the Socratic Schools.
描述
快速回复

您目前还是游客,请 登录注册